Sunday, August 18, 2019

Ethnic Diversity and Its Effect on the Welfare State: A Literature Review

Introduction
In the last half century, a considerable amount of research has been conducted by political scientists on the factors that impact the development of welfare states. However, comparatively little has been written on the effect of ethnic diversity on the provision of public goods, and researchers who have conducted work on the subject have found mixed results (Hjerm and Schnabel, 2012). There are various reasons to suspect that ethnic diversity may have a negative impact on welfare state generosity. In democracies, popular enthusiasm for economic redistribution may be dampened if poverty is associated with an ethnic minority (Soss and Sanford, 2007). Skilled political entrepreneurs may be able to take advantage of the economic anxieties and prejudices of the majority of the population to convince them to vote for political parties that promote free markets and small government through a process called ethnic outbidding. Furthermore, the different social, political, and economic preferences of ethnic groups may create problems with collective action (Alesina, Baqir, and Easterly, 1999). Consequently, legislatures in more diverse countries may have a more difficult time passing laws and increasing redistributive spending. Additionally, discrimination by law makers and bureaucrats against impoverished ethnic minorities in both the policy making and policy implementation process may lead to less spending on welfare (Schram, et al., 2009; Schram, et al., 2011). In authoritarian regimes, dictators can also use the uneven distribution of public goods to different ethnic groups as way to divide and weaken the opposition (Wood and Gough, 2006). As a result, more salient ethnic cleavages in dictatorships may lead to less spending on public goods. Nevertheless, in spite of the various mechanisms that can potentially link social cleavages to the size of the welfare state, many of the scholars who have conducted quantitative studies on the subject either found null results or a very weak relationship between the variables. Some scholars have ignored ethnicity all together. Why is this a neglected a topic? Furthermore, why have the studies that have been conducted on the subject found mixed results?  
            As will be shown, social cleavages can affect welfare distribution but only within certain contexts. Salient social cleavages intensified by political, economic, and social inequality between groups are more likely to have an impact on the size of the welfare state than cleavages that are not politicized (Steele, 2016). Diversity on its own is not necessarily an impediment to collective action. Furthermore, a review of the literature also shows that there is a considerable bias among comparative scholars towards focusing on welfare states in the developed world: specifically, Europe and East Asia. Most of the countries in these regions of the world have relatively homogeneous populations and a lack of the right type of social cleavages that could potentially have a negative impact on the development of welfare states (Alesina and Glaeser, 2004). Since these states consist of the vast majority of developed countries, there is a bias against studying the effect of social cleavages on welfare. One of the few developed countries with the right type of salient social cleavages that can potentially affect welfare state distribution is the United States; not coincidently, the bulk of the studies on this issue have been conducted by American political scientists. Studies on countries in the developing world such as Jordan (Baylouney, 2008), Syria (Eibl, 2016), Turkey (Yoruk, 2012), Kenya (Miguel and Gugerty, 2004), and Uganda (Habyarimana, Humphreys, Posner, and Weinstein, 2007) have also shown that social cleavages can negatively impact welfare distribution in certain contexts. 
            In this paper, I will first provide an overview of theories on the formation and size of welfare state that emerged from the work of comparative scholars who focused on countries in the developed world. As will be shown, these studies ignored social cleavages and focused on other political, economic, and social variables due to the nature of the countries they were studying.  Then, I will analyze the origins of scholarly work on the effect of ethnic cleavages on welfare spending in the United States, whose relatively unique demographics compared with other developed countries paved the way for studies on this subject. American political scientists introduced new statistical innovations that have enabled comparativists to analyze the impact of ethnic diversity on welfare state provision in large-n quantitative studies. Afterwards, I will analyze comparative studies that built on the work of American political scientists and have examined the effect of ethnic diversity across many countries in the developing world using new statistical innovations. While some of these works showed that ethnic diversity negatively effects spending on the welfare state and public goods in general, other studies have found null results. Finally, I will analyze scholarly work that have attempted to explain the reasons why ethnic diversity has inconsistent effects on public spending. As will be shown, the impact of ethnic diversity on welfare provision is highly dependent on the saliency of the ethnic cleavage and the nature of a country’s political institutions. 

Theories on the Formation and Size of Welfare States

            Before reviewing different theories on the welfare state, it is important to first define the concept. According to Irwin Garfinkel, Lee Rainwater, and Timothy Smeeding in their book Wealth and Welfare States
All wealthy nations, including the United States, are welfare states—that is, they are primarily capitalist states with large, selective doses of socialism. What has been socialized are institutions that reduce economic insecurity. By its nature, capitalism produced too much economic insecurity. A hall-mark objective of welfare state institutions is, therefore, to reduce economic insecurity. Education, health, and some forms of insurance all reduce economic insecurity. (Garfinkel, Rainwater, and Smeeding, 2)

While welfare states are generally found in wealthier nations, there is a high degree of variance in their scope and generosity. Furthermore, there are a great diversity of independent variables that can influence the development of the welfare state. To test theories that explain the divergence in public spending, comparative scholars from the 1970’s to the 2000’s collected data on welfare states—mainly countries in Western Europe and North America—and conducted regression analyses. The factors that impact the development of a welfare state can be broken down into economic, political, cultural, and international variables. 
            The impact of economics on the welfare state is one of the most commonly studied variables. According to Geof Wood and Ian Gough, public social spending on health, retirement pensions, unemployment insurance, family benefits, and education are expensive and require a certain level of domestic economic production before it becomes possible to pay for these benefits (Wood and Gough, 2006). Welfare states have their origins in Western European countries primarily because these they were the first to industrialize and urbanize. The wealth that was created from the industrial revolution provided states with the ability to obtain a greater amount of tax revenue to pay for these programs. Furthermore, industrial development also provides incentives for the government to invest in the welfare of their citizens. Investments in education and health lead to higher productivity, which in turn leads to higher economic growth. Welfare states can also be used to bolster political stability during an economic crisis. According to the political scientist David Cameron, the economic instability created by the booms and busts of capitalist markets and exposure to the fluctuating prices of goods that are traded internationally create a further incentive to establish a welfare state (Cameron, 1978). During economic downturns, the government can use spending on unemployment and family benefits to prevent protests and keep people out of poverty until the recession ends. This is why welfare state expansion usually does not take place during an economic boom but during times of economic insecurity when protests from below lead to governments making reforms (Piven and Cloward, 1971). 
            While welfare states first emerged in the West partially as a result of industrialization in the late nineteenth century, they later spread to different parts of the developing world as their economies developed throughout the second half of the twentieth century. Despite the claims of scholars like Garfinkel, Rainwater, and Smeeding, welfare states are not purely reserved for the wealthiest countries in the world. Most countries in East and South East Asia, Latin America, and the Middle East have developed welfare states although usually with less generous benefits than what is found in the West (Wood and Gough, 2006). In situations where resources are scarce, states may decide to limit the distribution of goods to groups that are seen as being potentially more loyal to the regime. This is referred to by Wood and Gough as a corporatist welfare state. Very poor countries that are dependent on agriculture and natural resources, such as the case in many countries in Sub-Saharan African, lack the necessary level economic development to afford welfare states and are highly dependent on foreign aid to provide basic services to their citizens.
            While economic development makes welfare states possible, there is still considerable variation in welfare spending among countries with similar GDP per capita. Economics alone cannot explain all of this variation. Political factors can either hinder or enable spending on welfare. One of those political variables is the strength of interest groups and their influence on the state (Huber and Stephens, 2001). Perhaps with the exception of spending on education, businessmen and other professions in the middle and upper class have far less interest in investing in the welfare state in comparison with the working class. Interest groups representing these wealthy groups are more likely to promote free market enterprise, low taxes, and small government. In contrast, socialist parties representing labor unions and the working class are far more likely to promote pro-welfare state policies. If left wing political parties and labor unions exert a greater influence on the government, the state is more likely to spend more money on social welfare policies. Evelyne Huber and John D. Stephens, in their book Development and Crisis of the Welfare State: Parties and Policies in Global Markets, prove that there exists a correlation between periods of left-wing government over the last half century and the size of welfare states throughout Western and Central Europe. Countries in Scandinavia, which were dominated for long periods of time by Social-Democratic parties from the 1950’s to the 1980’s, developed the most robust welfare states in Europe with the most generous benefits. In contrast, Great Britain, which has been more heavily influenced by liberal political interests, spends far less on its welfare state.  
            Differences in regime type can also affect the development of welfare states (Wood and Gough, 2006; Haggard and Kaufman, 2008). In democratic states, the establishment of welfare programs and labor regulations often have their origins in protest movements organized by labor unions and the political activity of left-wing political parties who mobilize voters and enact changes in democratically elected assemblies. Welfare states are thus a product of social movements from below. Benefits tend to be distributed relatively evenly across the population. In contrast, authoritarian governments are more likely to invest in the carceral state—police, the military, and the prison system—rather than solving social disputes through public social spending. Furthermore, when authoritarian regimes do invest in welfare, it is often to co-opt different groups to remain loyal to the regime. Benefits are usually distributed asymmetrically to some groups in society while excluding others. There are exceptions to the rule. According to Stephen Haggard and Robert Kaufman, in the book Development, Democracy, and Welfare States: Latin America, East Asia, and Eastern Europe, authoritarian systems that were communist or socialist gained their legitimacy by redistributing land and wealth to the working class (Haggard and Kaufman, 2008). Authoritarian regimes in Eastern Europe during the Cold War provided universal health, education, and employment for their citizens, although the quality of health and educational services was much weaker than in the Western welfare states. Overall, democratic states spend more on welfare on average than authoritarian states. 
            Long term cultural trends can also influence attitudes towards welfare spending, political institutions, and interest groups. Cultures that emphasize individualism, self-interest, and free markets are less likely to support economic redistribution than cultures that emphasize communal solidarity, public interest, and coordinated markets (Lipset, 1996). For example, Seymour Lipset claims that the origins of America’s relatively weak welfare state is a byproduct of a liberal consensus that has dominated the culture since its founding. This consensus is based on pluralistic democracy, the Protestant ethic, and capitalism. Advocates of this theory believe that America never had an aristocracy or a church hierarchy in its history since the country was founded by middle class immigrants that left Europe for economic opportunities. Without an upper class to overthrow and with abundant land available, Americans never developed class consciousness. There was no need for the same type of collective action and worker solidarity to expand the vote to white males. As a result, socialism never gained a strong footing on American soil. In comparison, states in Europe have long feudal histories, and class solidarity and social protest was required to overthrow states where monarchies, aristocracies, and the hierarchal church organizations had privileged positions. This is exemplified in revolutions that took place in France in 1789 and Russia in 1917.  Consequently, continental Europe developed a culture that had a more positive attitude towards unions and welfare redistribution that the United States. 
            Along with the economic, political, and cultural factors noted above, the international community can also affect welfare state development. The spread of welfare state policies can happen as a result of cultural diffusion as publics and governments become aware of policy innovations in other states (Dolowitz and Marsh, 2000). Furthermore, international institutions and powerful governments can persuade or pressure weaker governments to enact reforms that positively or negatively affect the welfare state. For example, the International Monetary Fund has often pressured countries struggling with debt to make cuts to public spending to balance the budget (Marsh and Sharman, 2009). Additionally, some scholars have argued that an increase in international trade will lead to greater spending on welfare programs. Greater exposure to the international market place means greater economic instability, which may lead to governments increasing the size of the welfare state to deal with the flux in international prices (Cameron, 1978). In contrast, other scholars have argued that an increase in international trade will lead to a smaller welfare state (Jensen and Lindstadt, 2012). Globalization has increased the power of corporations to take their businesses abroad to take advantage of cheap labor, which may have created a race to the bottom as countries seek to attract companies to their shores with lower tax rates and looser regulations. Globalization may explain why many Western countries have made cuts to their welfare states since the 1980’s.
            While the studies cited above contributed greatly to our understanding of the welfare state, what most of them have in common is that they neglected to discuss the role of ethnicity on the distribution of public goods. Until the late 1990’s, it was a neglected topic (Alesina and Glaesar, 2004). However, statistical innovations by American political scientists have since enabled comparative scholars to study the effect of ethnicity on public spending across countries. 

American Political Science: Analyzing the Effect of Ethnic Diversity on the Welfare State
            The first studies on the effect of ethnic diversity on welfare state expansion were conducted mainly by American political scientists. There were a variety of reasons for this. By the late nineteenth and twentieth century, most European states were relatively homogenous and had developed strong national identities backed by a common language, religion, and national culture (Alesina and Glaesar, 2004). These national identities were a product of several centuries of inter-state warfare and state building on the European continent. Societal cleavages over economic redistribution and the expansion of the welfare state tended to be based on class and not ethnicity. In contrast, the United States developed a multi-cultural identity due to years of migration—voluntary and forced--from different parts of the globe. Consequently, the United States had substantial African American, European Catholic and Latino minorities that were substantially poorer than the White Protestant European majority. The issues of race and language were fundamentally tied into questions of economic redistribution in American politics.
One of the first American studies on ethnicity and its impact on the welfare state in America was the 1971 book Regulating the Poor: The Functions of Public Welfareby Frances Fox Piven and Richard Cloward (Piven and Cloward, 1971). In the book, the authors contradict what was a widely held view that welfare programs were established due to left wing shifts in ideology and the moral need to help the poor during depressed economic conditions. Instead, Piven and Cloward argue that welfare states are established as a response by the wealthy elite to regime threatening protests from social forces below. To demobilize protestors, the state will increase welfare benefits, but they will retract those benefits once the protests die down. To test the theory, they analyzed the two major episodes of welfare state expansion in the United States: Franklin Roosevelt’s New Deal (1933-37) and Lyndon Johnson’s Great Society programs (1964-68). During the Great Depression in the 1930’s, the US federal government created Social Security, unemployment insurance, and poverty relief programs for the first time, taking on a role once played by local governments and private charity networks. FDR’s government did this not because of the poverty created by the Great Depression but the growth of urban social protest and the rise of radical left-wing movements. Welfare benefits though were specifically targeted at white urban communities as blacks in rural communities in the Jim Crow South were systematically discriminated against and lacked the resources to mobilize. Farmers and domestic servants were excluded from the Social Security roles. Using primary documents, Piven and Cloward also show how white welfare case workers found creative ways to exclude blacks who should have qualified for benefits but were kept off the welfare rolls anyway. Following the decline of protests in the late 1930’s, many of the poverty and work relief programs established by the New Deal were cut back. 
The second case of welfare state expansion in American history, which took place in the 1960’s, was precipitated by the migration of Southern Blacks from the Jim Crow South to cities in the North East and West coast in the 1940’s and 1950’s. With their jobs as farmers replaced by modern machinery, rural blacks were forced to migrate to northern cities, which led to the rise of poverty in urban centers throughout the country and the rise in the number of protests among urban blacks. This political unrest was tied into the Civil Rights movements. With greater access to resources in cities, black communities throughout the country were able to exert more pressure on the state. To deal with the growing power of black voters, Lyndon Johnson’s administration passed a series of reforms that enabled urban black communities to gain greater access to federal welfare services, which included public housing, food stamps, and Aid for Impoverished Families with Dependent Children. These reforms coincided with the passing of the Civil Rights act of 1964 and the Voting Rights Act of 1965 as well as the creation of Medicare and Medicaid, which provided access to public healthcare for the elderly and the poor. From 1964 to 1968, the welfare rolls for the Aid for Families with Dependent Children program rose as did the number of people with access to public housing. The rise in the number of blacks on welfare though created a backlash against the welfare state among the majority of whites. After 1968 when protests died down in the black community, welfare benefits were subsequently retrenched. 
            While qualitative and inductive historical works like Piven’s and Cloward’s book established the idea that ethnic diversity can potentially have a negative impact on welfare distribution, cross-national quantitative works were not conducted to test the theory until the late 1990’s due to data limitations. One of the pioneering studies on the subject was conducted by Alberto Alesina, Reza Baqir and William Easterly in the article “Public Goods and Ethnic Divisions.” (Alesina, Baqir, and Easterly, 1999). In the article, the authors analyze the reasons why some local governments in the United States spend more on public goods provision than others. They contribute to the literature by showing that ethnic diversity has a negative effect on public goods provision. They theorize that different ethnic groups may have different preferences, which will potentially create more gridlock in the legislature. Furthermore, they argue that the ethnic majority may be less likely to support the distribution of resources to the poor through welfare spending if the poor are associated with minorities. This leads to a phenomenon that the authors call welfare chauvinism. To test this theory, the authors analyzed the effect of ethnic diversity on public spending on education, sewage systems, roads, health, trash disposal, health, and policing in US cities, metropolitan areas, and urban counties in the year 1990. To measure ethnic diversity, they used the ethno-fractionalization index, a dataset that had been recently created by Alberto Alesina. The index calculated the chances that two random individuals chosen from a population were of a different ethnicity—by ethnicity, they specifically mean linguistic, religious, and racial groups. In the study, they control for variables that can also impact spending such as the city’s GDP per capita, the size of the city, the level of education, average age, and income inequality. They also control for other factors that can affect the public budget like deficit spending, overall debt, and intergovernmental transfers. As predicted, ethnic diversity had a negative impact on spending on education, roads, sewer, and trash pickup, and it had a positive effect on police spending, deficit spending, and the debt.After the publication of this study, numerous American scholars have used quantitative methods to show that greater racial diversity at the local and state level has negatively impacted the amount of government spending on welfare and other public goods. 
Scholars also began to use quantitative methods to compare the American welfare state with countries in Western Europe and analyze the impact of ethnic diversity on the size of welfare states across countries. Alberto Alesina and Edward Glaeser, in the book Fighting Poverty in the US and Europe: A World of Difference, analyze the following research question: why do states in Western Europe have more extensive welfare states than America? (Alesina and Glaeser, 2004) Alesina and Glaeser argue that the past scholars who have approached this question have failed to back their conclusions with empirical evidence. In the past, numerous scholars have theorized that the US may have a weaker welfare state because the country has more economic mobility, is less efficient at collecting taxes, and is less exposed to external shocks from the international marketplace than smaller European countries. However, Alesina and Glaeser use OECD data to show that the US is not more economically mobile than European countries, does not have more problems than Europe in terms of collecting taxes, and actually has an economy that has more booms and busts that Western European states since its political economy is more liberal. Instead, Alesina and Glaeser argue that two interconnected variables explain the disparity in welfare spending between the United States and Europe: the structure of institutions and ethnicity. 
According to Alesina and Glaeser, institutions that create more veto points such as presidential systems, bicameral houses, and federalism are more likely to decrease welfare spending since it becomes harder to pass legislation and it is easier for minority interests to block reform. In contrast, parliamentary systems, unicameral legislatures, and unitary political systems make passing legislation easier. In parliamentary systems of government found in Western European countries, the powers of the executive and the legislative branch are fused together since the majority of representatives in parliament choose the prime minister. With a relative lack of checks and balances, these types of systems have made it easier for left wing governments to pass welfare reform when they come into power. All they need to do is win one round of parliamentary elections. Once welfare reform is passed, it subsequently becomes difficult to cutback benefits in the future as they become popular with the public. In contrast, presidential systems such as the United States divide power between the executive and legislative branches, which often leads to divided government and gridlock. This partly explains why states in Western and Central Europe spend more on public welfare than the United States and Latin America. Furthermore, Alessina and Glaesar argue that federal political systems are correlated with less spending on welfare than unitary systems. Federal political systems that devolve some powers to local subunits also make it more difficult to increase overall welfare spending since passing reforms has to be done in each locality separately. Additionally, Alesina and Glaeser argue that single member district electoral systems that promote a two-party system make welfare state reforms less likely since they make it more difficult for emerging third parties on the left to gain political support and win seats in the legislature. Proportional electoral systems, which award seats to third parties even if they get a small percentage of the vote, encourage more ideological diversity. While third parties representing the interest of labor began winning seats in parliaments throughout Western Europe in the late nineteenth century, socialist parties in the United States struggled electorally to make any ground politically. Overall, the structure of America’s institutions has benefited the wealthy elite who are in favor of economically liberal policies. 
Alesina and Glaesar also argue that salient ethnic cleavages explain much of the variation in welfare spending between the United States and Western Europe. Most Western European countries have relatively homogenous populations, and countries that do have social cleavages such as Switzerland and Belgium are not economically salient. In other words, there are no large wealth gaps between ethnic minorities and majorities in Western European states. In contrast, the history of slavery in the United States and the mass migration of Catholics from Europe and Hispanics from Latin America created a group of ethnic minorities that were substantially poorer than the majority of the population. Prior to the 1960’s, African Americans in the South were systematically discriminated against and kept off of welfare rolls. Since Lyndon Johnson’s expansion of welfare to urban black communities in the 1960’s, right wing politicians have successfully framed welfare programs as the government redistribution of wealth towards underserving ethnic minorities.  More importantly, Alesina and Glaesar argue that America’s heterogenous demographics is tied into the structure of its institutions. America’s diversity created ethnic divides between the country’s working class, which significantly weakened the power of labor unions. It also made it relatively easier in America for right wing politicians to divide the working class by race and language. Consequently, political institutions that benefited the country’s capitalist elite did not face significant pressure for reform from social forces below. In Western Europe states, their current democratic institutions came into being as a result of a homogenous working-class protesting for reforms to the electoral system and the structure of political institutions in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century. 
To test their theories, Alesina and Glaesar utilized a mixed method approach. For their quantitative analysis, they used OECD data to measure retirement benefits, unemployment insurance, disability benefits, family transfers, and healthcare spending over the course of a half century. They also analyzed laws and regulation that protect workers such as the minimum wage. They compared this data across Western countries with the types of institutions found in each country and the degree of ethnic diversity. They also controlled for variables like GDP per capita. The authors found that institutions explain approximately half of the variation in welfare spending across Western states while ethnic diversity explains the other half. Furthermore, Alesina and Glaesar also conducted a qualitative analysis of each country in the study. They used primary historical documents to connect the structure of institutions and ethnic cleavages to welfare spending. This method of causal process tracing complemented their quantitative approach and showed how ethnic cleavages in the United States directly led to less spending on welfare. 
Since the publication of these innovative works, many other American political scientists have found similar conclusions. Several studies have shown that racial diversity in the United States has allowed right wing politicians to frame means tested welfare programs as benefits targeted towards minorities (Soss and Schram, 2001). This has made white Americans less likely to support the redistribution of wealth towards the poor. Past studies on racial resentment and symbolic racism have also shown that white attitudes towards blacks is tied into their perceptions of who benefits disproportionately from welfare policies. While studies show that traditional Jim-Crow style racism has declined in the United States since the 1960’s, the same studies also show that many whites still harbor racial resentment and believe that ethnic minorities are abusing welfare programs and leeching off the state (Bobo, Kluegel, and Smith, 1997; Tarman and Sears, 2005). Other studies have shown that America’s heterogenous culture made it more difficult for the working class to coalesce, which has weakened the ability of America’s labor unions to enact policy change at the federal level (Lieberman, 2003). The consequence of this is that America’s welfare state is more decentralized and fragmented, and the country’s labor unions are weaker politically than those in Western Europe. Other scholars have found that when the design of American welfare policies is decentralized and controlled by local governments, welfare policy tends to involve greater sanctioning of welfare recipients, the distribution of fewer welfare benefits, and more resources spent on policing (Soss, Fording, and Schram, 2008). For example, when the program Aid for Families with Dependent Children (AFDC) was replaced with the more restrictive program Temporary Assistance for Needy Families (TANF) in 1996, control over welfare policy was decentralized to the local level and communities with a higher proportion of minorities saw the creation of more punitive rules and harder access to welfare benefits. While the intent of the program was to increase the efficiency of welfare distribution and punish free riders, it also led to more discrimination against minorities. Furthermore, studies have also shown that when bureaucrats have discretion over the distribution of welfare benefits to families, they are more likely to engage in sanctioning when there are more minorities in their locality (Schram, et al., 2009; Schram, et al., 2011). At least within America’s historical context, ethnic diversity has had a negative effect on the size of the welfare state. 



Studies from the Developing World: Finding Mixed Results
             While American scholars have created a substantial body of qualitative and quantitative evidence to show that ethnic diversity can have a negative impact on welfare spending, these studies are mired by the problem of external validity. While ethnic diversity in America may have led to less welfare spending in comparison with homogenous Western European states, will this same theory apply to other countries that are also ethnically diverse? In other words, does the United States relatively unique history make it an outlier? Starting in the 2000’s, comparativists began using data sets that measure ethnic diversity to conduct large-n studies on welfare states and public spending. Unlike Alesina’s and Glaeser’s study, many of these studies went beyond Western Europe and the United States. Some scholars have offered evidence that ethnic diversity can have a negative effect on public goods provision; however, other studies found null or weak results. 
Several medium and small-n studies revealed that there are countries in the developing world where ethnic diversity has had an impact on the size of the welfare state. For example, Ferdinand Eibl, in the dissertation “Social Dictatorships: The Political Economy of the Welfare State in the Middle East and North Africa,” demonstrates that politicized ethnic cleavages had a negative impact on welfare spending in the Middle East and North Africa (Eibl, 2016). In this work, he analyzes the reasons why spending on the welfare state differs across the following lower middle-income countries (GDP per capita between $3,000-$10,000/year) in the Middle East and North Africa since the 1950’s: Egypt, Iran (pre and post 1979), Jordan, Syria, Morocco, and Tunisia. Among these countries, Tunisia and Iran (post 1979 revolution) have relatively robust welfare states with universal coverage in terms of health care, retirement pensions, and unemployment. In contrast, Morocco, Jordan, and Iran (pre-1979) have relatively weak welfare states with only a minority of the population—mainly public sector workers and military personal--receiving benefits. Egypt and Syria are in the middle of pack in terms of spending on welfare. 
Ferdinand Eibl argues that several different variables explain variation across these states. For one, the size of the welfare state is impacted by the nature of the coalition that was formed by the autocrat when the ruling regime came into being following the end of colonization. New regimes that had to make an alliance with labor organizations to establish a base of power, as was the case in Tunisia, Egypt, Syria, and Iran (post 1979), established a more robust welfare state. Regimes that had right wing coalitions upon independence, as was with the case with the monarchies in Morocco, Jordan, and Iran (pre-1979), had far weaker welfare states characterized by the uneven distribution of welfare to military personal and public sector workers. Furthermore, states that had to spend more on their military due to international conflict had less resources to spend on social welfare. In the literature, this is known as the “guns for butter” tradeoff. States like Egypt, Syria, and Jordan spent large percentages of their public budget on their military due to their involvement in the Israeli-Palestinian conflict, and Iran spent large sums on its war with Iraq in the 1980’s. Access to oil rents also had a significant impact on the welfare state. The only one of these countries with significant amounts of petroleum reserves is Iran, and this helped the country offset the expensive costs of military conflict to establish a robust welfare state in the 1980’s following the Islamic Revolution in 1979. Finally, salient social cleavages also explain some of the variation among these welfare states. When dictators rule over states with salient ethnic cleavages, they can play those ethnic groups against each other through the strategy of divide and conquer. Consequently, dictators can distribute less resources to ethnic groups outside the ruling coalition but still maintain their base of power. In the case of Syria, the ruling Alawite coalition—approximately 15 percent of the country’s population—receives a disproportionate share of public resources in comparison with the country’s Sunni Muslim majority. In Jordan, the country’s Palestinian migrants, which are now approximately half of the population, are systematically discriminated against by the state while those descended from tribes that live to the East of the Jordan river receive a disproportionate share of welfare benefits and jobs in the public sector. In contrast, a state like Tunisia is ethnically homogenous, and its working class is not divided by religion, race, or language. To test each of his theories, Ferdinand Eibl uses an impressive mix of quantitative and qualitative evidence. Using data from the International Monetary Fund, he conducted a quantitative analysis of these countries from 1960 to 2015. Controlling for a large number of socioeconomic and political variables, he showed how the ideological nature of ruling coalitions, the amount of spending on the military, the amount of oil reserves, and the presence of salient ethnic cleavages each had a statistically significant impact on the size of their welfare states. He complemented this data analysis with an historical comparison of each of these case studies. 
            There are many other examples of researchers who have found a correlation between ethnic cleavages and spending on welfare states and public spending in the developing world.  James Habyarimana, Macartan Humphreys, Daniel Posner, and Jeremy Weinstein, in a series of experiments conducted in the capital of Uganda, found that individuals that are co-ethnics are better able to cooperate in the distribution of public goods to the community since co-ethnics are better able to engage in collective action (Habyarimana, Humphreys, Posner, and Weinstein, 2007). Co-ethnics have more tightly knit communities based on trust between individuals, and individuals within these communities can better monitor and sanction free riders.  In another example, Erdem Yoruk, in the article "Shifting forms of Turkish State Paternalism toward the Kurds: Social Assistance as Benevolent Control," demonstrates how the Turkish state discriminated against its Kurdish minority throughout the twentieth century (Yoruk, 2012). Even when the Turkish state began to distribute more public resources to Kurdish communities in the 2000’s, it did so unevenly and in an authoritarian manner as a means to maintain social control. Local communities in Kurdistan were denied local autonomy over their own resources. Overall, Kurdistan still receives a disproportionally smaller share of public resources than the rest of Turkey. There are many other case examples of countries with salient ethnic cleavages that have witnessed conflict over the asymmetrical distribution of resources (Horowitz, 1985).  
While many small and medium-n have found that ethnic diversity impacts the distribution of welfare in different parts of the developing world, many quantitative large-n studies have found mixed or null results. For example, Eric Kramon and Daniel Posner, in the article “Who Benefits from Distributive Politics? How the Outcome One Studies Affects the Answer One Gets,” claim in their literature review that past large-n studies on the effect of ethnic diversity on the distribution of public goods have produced mixed results (Kramon and Posner, 2013) They argue that the results of a quantitative analysis is impacted by the way one measures public goods. To test this theory, the authors compared six different countries in Sub Saharan Africa. To analyze the impact of ethnicity on public goods provision, they looked at which ethnic group controlled the presidency. To compare access to public goods across ethnic groups, they compared each communities access to medical care, education, water, and electricity. They measured this by looking at infant mortality, average years of schooling, average access to water, and average access to electricity. Utilizing a quasi-experimental difference-in-difference design, they analyzed how access to these goods for each community changed when a president from a different ethnic group came into power. If the theory that ethnicity affects the distribution of public goods is true, we should expect that ethnic groups will benefit more when a president from their ethnicity comes into power. The authors find that the results of the analysis change depending on what public good is measured. With some public goods, the ethnicity of the president has an impact but with other goods it does not. There are also different results across countries. Unfortunately, the authors in this do not attempt to give an explanation for why there are mixed results or why there are differences across countries. 
Many other quantitative studies have found that ethnic diversity has no impact or a mixed impact on the welfare state and public goods provision (Baldwin and Huber, 2010; Steele, 2016; Miguel and Gugerty, 2016). Why were scholars achieving mixed results in their quantitative studies despite the large amount of qualitative evidence that ethnic diversity has impacted the distribution of welfare in many case studies?
             
Explanations for Mixed Results: Analyzing the Saliency of Ethnic Cleavages
            Beginning in the late 2000’s, scholars began shifting their focus to understanding why the impact of ethnic diversity on the welfare state differed from one country to another. As opposed to seeing ethnic cleavages as being similar across all states, these scholars approached the subject with the understanding that ethnic divides across countries can differ in terms of their saliency; in other words, larger political, economic, and cultural gaps between groups will lead to more tension between them. In some states, ethnic groups coexist relatively peacefully, and strong national identities have overcome ethnic and regional differences (Miguel and Gugerty, 2004). In other cases, ethnic groups have engaged in conflict and national identities are relatively weak.  For example, salient ethnic cleavages may impact the welfare state in America, but Germany’s Protestant-Catholic divide is not a politicized cleavage that has impacted spending on public goods. Instead of only looking at whether or not a state is diverse using Alesina’s Ethno-fractionalization index, scholars have begun using new statistics that measure the saliency of ethnic cleavages (Steele, 2016). Furthermore, scholars also began to breakdown ethnic identity--language, religion, and race—into its different components to see if different forms of ethnicity had different impacts on welfare state spending. Finally, other political scientists began analyzing the impact of institutions on ethnic cleavages to see if ethnic divides could be mitigated by institutional structures. 
One of the authors that have attempted to explain why the results of past quantitative studies were mixed is Liza Steele. In the article “Ethnic Diversity and Support for Redistributive Social Polices,” Steele analyzes the reasons why ethnic diversity can have a varied effect on the amount of welfare spending (Steele, 2016). She theorizes that ethnic diversity can potentially have a negative impact on welfare spending, but this is highly dependent on whether the ethnic cleavage is politicized. It is also dependent on the size of the wealth gap between ethnic groups. The more politicized a cleavage and the larger the wealth gap, the more like it is to find the existence of welfare chauvinism, which is when welfare becomes associated with a minority group. To test this theory, the author conducted over 100 different regression analyses with data pooled together from 91 different countries. As a robustness check, the author uses multiple measurements of welfare spending from the World Bank development indicators, the Standard Income Inequality data base, and the Economic Freedom of the World dataset. The author also analyzes the World Values Survey to measure level of support for the welfare state across countries. To measure the independent variable, the author uses a variety of different datasets. Along with using Alesina’s Ethno-fractionalization Index, the author also uses data sets that measure the saliency of ethnic cleavages across countries. To measure the amount of political inequality, the author uses the Ethnic Power Relations dataset. This dataset measures whether ethnic groups in a country share power in the executive branch or if only one ethnic group dominates the government at the expense of others. Liza Steele also uses Ted Gurr’s Minorities at Risk dataset, which analyzes the degree to which demographically significant minority groups faces political oppression, and she also used a dataset that measures amount of immigration that takes place per year. Finally, the author also controls for a large number of socioeconomic and institutional variables that can potentially impact the size of welfare states. As predicted, ethnic diversity only had an impact on welfare spending across states depending on the nature of the ethnic cleavage and the degree of inequality between groups. Measurements of political and economic inequality between ethnic groups had a statistically negative effect on welfare spending, but ethnic diversity on its own had no significant effect. Immigration only had a negative effect on welfare spending when it was coupled with high rates of inequality in society. This study is impressive in terms of the larger number of robustness checks and the extensive number of control variables. 
            Other studies have shown similar results. Kate Baldwin and John Huber, in the article “Economic versus Cultural Differences: Forms of Ethnic Diversity and Public Goods Provision,” also analyzed the effect of ethnic diversity on the provision of public goods (Baldwin and Huber, 2010). The authors claim that past studies on the subject found mixed results because they only used Alberto Alesina’s Ethno-fractionalization Index to measure ethnic diversity. Baldwin and Huber argue that it is not ethnic diversity that matters but the nature of the relationship between different groups. They argue that larger amounts of economic and cultural inequality between groups will lead to more hatred, which in turn will lead to ethnic chauvinism and less redistribution of public goods. Baldwin and Huber also theorize that greater cultural differences between groups in terms of language will make collective action more difficult. To test these two theories, the authors analyze the impact of inequality between groups on public goods spending in 46 countries form the years 1996 to 2006. To measure their dependent variable, they look at ten different statistics from the World Bank’s data base on public health, education, tax capacity, and infrastructure. To measure economic inequality between groups, they developed a new statistic called Between Group Inequality (BGI index). To measure cultural inequality, they use James Fearon’s Linguistic Fractionalization Index. They also did a separate analysis using Alesina’s Ethno-fractionalization Index. The authors controlled for GDP per capita, regime type (Polity IV), and the size of the population.  The results showed that only the BGI index had a statistically negative effect on public goods spending. In other words, ethnic diversity was more likely to impact public spending when there was a large wealth gap between ethnic groups.
What these studies show is that ethnic diversity does not necessarily mean that the country will struggle more with collective action or that ethnic minorities will be systematically discriminated against. Different institutional arrangements and public policy decisions can mitigate the potential problems caused by ethnic diversity. Arend Lijphart, in the article “Constitutional Design for Divided Societies,” analyzes the reasons why the relationship between ethnic groups differs across countries (Lijphart, 2004). In the work, the author offers a synthesis of his past works on the subject. According to Lijphart, certain types of institutions make it more likely for ethnic groups to coexist in peace and engage in collective action with one another. For example, federalism gives ethnic groups that are concentrated in peripheral regions some autonomy, which includes control of taxation and public spending at the local level. Furthermore, proportional electoral systems at the national level encourage the formation of more political parties and allows smaller minorities greater representation in the legislature. In addition, having quotas in the executive branch in the bureaucracies gives minorities greater representation in institutions responsible for the distribution of public goods and services, which can potentially decrease the amount of discrimination against ethnic minorities. Other scholars have demonstrated that states that deliberately try to promote a national identity and discourage regional and ethnic identities over the long term can create stronger states that distribute more goods and services. For example, Edward Miguel and Mary Kay Gugerty, in the article “Tribe or Nation? Nation Building and Public Goods in Kenya versus Tanzania,” demonstrates that local level governments in Tanzania are better able to raise and spend money on education and infrastructure than local governments in Kenya because the Tanzanian government has made far greater efforts to foster a national identity at the expense of regional tribal identities over the last half century (Miguel and Gugerty, 2004). This includes promoting a common language and national historical heritage in schools. This is why diversity only had a negative impact on public spending in Kenya. Of course, this process of nation building also leads to the loss of local linguistic and cultural diversity overtime, but it also creates a common sense of identity across the state. 
            While most of the recent scholarship has argued that the impact of ethnicity on the welfare states depends heavily on the saliency of the social cleavage, it is important to note that not all political scientists agree (Soifer, 2016). Some scholars have tried to show that there are variables that explain both the existence of salient ethnic cleavages and the amount of spending on welfare and other public goods. For example, Andreas Wimmer, in the article “Is Diversity Detrimental? Ethnic Fractionalization, Public Goods Provision, and the Historical Legacies of Stateness,” argues that salient ethnic cleavages and the amount of public goods provision are both explained by the level of state capacity. In the article, Wimmer analyzes the reasons why some countries spend more on the distribution of public goods than others (Wimmer, 2016). Specifically, he focuses on the effect of ethnic diversity on public goods provision. The author argues that past studies that have shown that diversity has a negative effect on public goods provision failed to control for the impact of state capacity on the distribution of public goods. Wimmer claims that state capacity can explain both the level of ethnic diversity and the state’s ability to distribute public goods. States that have a high degree of capacity can foster a strong sense of national identity by establishing educational institutions, building an infrastructure, and facilitating communication across the country. Furthermore, greater state capacity means a greater ability to tax and spend. To test this theory, the author first conducted a large-n quantitative analysis of the effect of ethnic diversity on public goods provision in the developing world. To measure ethnic diversity, the author uses the Ethnic Power Relations Index, which analyzes the degree of political inequality between ethnic groups in a country. The assumption is that states with less salient ethnic cleavages will distribute more public goods.  To measure public goods provision across many states, they used measurements for literacy rates, infant mortality, and railroad tracks per kilometer. To measure state capacity, the authors used a new data set to determine if a state had a bureaucratic structure prior to European colonialism. States like China that had a bureaucratic structure prior to colonialism are assumed to have more state capacity upon independence form European influence than states like the Democratic Republic of the Congo. The authors controlled for a wide range of geographic, economic, social, and political variables. First, they conducted an analysis without the measure for state capacity and found that salient ethnic cleavages had a negative effect on public goods provision. However, when the measurement for state capacity was added, salient ethnic cleavages had no effect and state capacity had a positive impact on the provision of public goods. Of course, this study only analyzes a couple of different public goods and does not directly analyze public spending on welfare provision. 

Conclusion
            While there are critics of the theory that ethnic diversity has a negative impact on the welfare state, there is also a substantial body of qualitative and quantitative evidence in support of it. Ethnic diversity can negatively affect the distribution of welfare and public goods in general depending on the nature of the ethnic cleavage and the good being distributed. However, ethnic diversity on its own does not necessarily mean that groups will struggle over the distribution of resources. Institutional reforms and the fostering of a strong national identity can mitigate the relationship between ethnic groups and improve the state’s capacity to develop a robust welfare state across ethnic lines. 
While the work completed on this subject has grown more sophisticated in recent years, there are still significant gaps in the literature. Recent work on the subject has focused on understanding how the saliency of the ethnic cleavage impacts welfare spending, but far less work has been done understanding how the nature of the public good impacts the results of a study. Are ethnic cleavages more likely to impact spending on welfare in comparison with spending on other public goods such as infrastructure or the military? Furthermore, are there differences across welfare programs? For example, evidence from several studies in the United States and other countries indicates that racial and class cleavages have a more negative impact on means tested welfare programs like TANF benefits than universal programs like Social Security (Jordan, 2013).  It is easier to frame a welfare program as being targeted at a minority group when the program is only utilized by the poor or an ethnic minority. Are there similar interactions between spending on other types of public goods and ethnic cleavages? 











Work Cited
Alesina Alberto, Reza Baqir, and William Easterly. 1999. “Public Goods and Ethnic Divisions,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114(4): 1243-1284.

Alesina, Alberto, and Edward L. Glaeser. 2004. Fighting Poverty in the US and Europe: A World of Difference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Baylouny, Anne Marie. 2008. “Militarizing Welfare: Neo-liberalism and Jordanian policy,” The Middle East Journal, 62(2): 277-303.
Bobo, Lawrence, James R. Kluegel, and Ryan A, Smith. 1997. "Laissez-Faire Racism: The Crystallization of a 'Kindler, Gentler' Anti-black Ideolog," in Racial Attitudes in the 1990s: Continuity and Change, edited by Steven A. Tuch and Jack K. Martin. Praeger Publishing: Connecticut.
Bloom, Pazit Ben-nun, Gizem Arikan, and Marie Courtemanche. 2015. "Religious social identity, religious belief, and anti-immigration sentiment," American Political Science Review, 109(2): 203-221.
Boushey, Graeme. 2016. "Targeted for Diffusion? How the Use and Acceptance of Stereotypes Shape the Diffusion of Criminal Justice Policy Innovations in the American States," American Political Science Review,110(1): 198-214.
Cameron, David. 1978. "The Expansion of the Public Economy: A Comparative Analysis," American Political Science Review, 72(4): 1243-61.
DeSante, Christopher D. 2013. “Working Twice as Hard to Get Half as Far: Race, Work Ethic, and America's Deserving Poor,” American Journal of Political Science, 57(2): 342-356.
Ditonto, Tessa M., Richard R. Lau and David O. Sears. 2013. “AMPing Racial Attitudes: Comparing the Power of Explicit and Implicit Racism Measures in 2008,” Political Psychology, 34(4).
Dixon, Jeffrey C. and Michael S. Rosenbaum. 2004. “Nice to Know You? Testing Contact, Cultural, and Group Threat Theories of Anti-Black and Anti-Hispanic Stereotypes,” Social Science Quarterly, 85(2).
Dolowitz, David P. and David Marsh. 2000. “Learning from Abroad: The Role of Policy Transfer in Contemporary Policy-Making,” Governance: An International Journal of Policy and Administration, 13(1): 5-24.
Eibl, Ferdinand.  2016. "Social Dictatorships: The Political Economy of the Welfare State in the Middle East and North Africa," Dissertation for St. Antony's College.
Enos, Ryan D. 2016. "What the demolition of public housing teaches us about the impact of racial threat on political behavior," American Journal of Political Science, 60(1): 123-142.
Haggard, Stephan and Robert Kaufman. 2008. Development, Democracy, and Welfare States: Latin America, East Asia, and Eastern Europe.  Princeton University Press: Princeton.
Hartman, Todd K., Benjamin J. Newman, and C. Scott Bell. 2014. "Decoding Prejudice Toward Hispanics: Group Cues and Public Reactions to Threatening Immigrant Behavior," Political Behavior, 36: 143-163.
Hjerm, Mikael and Annette Schnabel. 2012. "How Much Heterogeneity Can the Welfare State Endure? The Influence of Heterogeneity on Attitudes towards the Welfare state," Nations and Nationalism, 18: 346-369.
Huber, Evelyne and John D. Stephens.  Development and Crisis of the Welfare State: Parties and Policies in Global Markets.  The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, 2001.
Huber, Gregory A. and John S. Lapinski. 2006. “The ‘Race Card’ Revisited: Assessing Racial Priming in Policy Contests,” American Journal of Political Science, 50(2): 421–440.
Kinder, Donald and David Sears. 1981. “Prejudice and Politics: Symbolic Racism Versus Racial Threats to the Good Life," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 40(3): 414-431.
Jawad, Rana. “Review Essay: Possibilities of Positive Social Action in the Middle East: A Re-Reading of the History of Social Policy in the Region.” Global Social Policy 8, no. 2 (2008): 267–280.
Jensen, Nathan M., and Rene Lindstadt. 2012. "Leaning Right and Learning from the Left: Diffusion of Corporate Tax Policy Across Borders," Comparative Political Studies, 45(3): 283-311.
Jordan, Jason. 2013. “Policy feedback and support for the welfare state,” Journal of European Social Policy23(2): 134-148.
Lieberman, Robert. 2003. "Chapter One: Race and the Limits of Solidarity: American Welfare State Development in the Comparative Perspective," in the book Race and Welfare Reform, edited by Sanford Schram, Joe Soss, and Richard Fording. University of Michigan Press: Michigan. 
Lijphart, Arend. 2004. “Constitutional Design for Divided Societies,” Journal of Democracy, 15(4): 96-109.

Lipset, Seymour. American Exceptionalism: A Double-Edged Sword. W.W. Norton: New York, 1996.
Marsh, David and J. C. Sharman. 2009. “Policy Diffusion and policy Transfer,” Policy Studies, 30 (3): 269-288.
Massoud, Karshenas, Valentine M. Moghadam, and Randa Alami. 2014. “Social Policy after the Arab Spring: States and Social Rights in the MENA Region,” World Development, 64: 726–739.
Miguel, Edward and Mary Kay Gugerty. 2004. “Tribe or Nation? Nation Building and Public
Goods in Kenya versus Tanzania,” World Politics, 56(April): 327-362.

Nail, Paul R., Helen C. Harton, and Brian P. Decker. 2003. "Political Orientation and Modern versus Aversive Racism: Tests of Dovidio and Gaertner's (1998) Integrated Model,"Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 84(4): 754.
Newman, Benjamin J. 2013. “Acculturating Contexts and Anglo Opposition to Immigration in the United States,” The American Journal of Political Science, 57(2):  374-390.
Owens, Michael Leo and Adrienne Smith. 2012. "'Deviants' and Democracy: Punative Policy Designs and the Social Rights of Felons as Citizens," American Politics Research, 40: 531-67.
Piven, Frances Fox and Richard Cloward. 1971. Regulating the Poor: The Functions of Public Welfare. Pantheon Books: New York.
Quillian, Lincoln. 2008. “Does Unconscious Racism Exist?” Social Psychology Quarterly, 71(1): 6–11.
Schneider, A., and H. Ingram. 1993. “Social Construction of Target Populations: Implications for Politics and Policy,” American Political Science Review, 87(2):334-47.
Schram, Sanford, Joe Soss, Richard Fording, and Linda Houser. 2009. ‘‘Deciding to Discipline: Race, Politics, and Punishment at the Front Lines of Welfare Reform,’’ American Sociological Review, 74 (3): 398–422.
Sniderman, Paul M., Thomas Piazza, Philip E. Tetlock, Ann Kendrick. 1991. “The New Racism,” The American Journal of Political Science, 35(2): 423-447.
Soifer, Hillel D. 2016. "Regionalism, Ethnic Diversity, and Variation in Public Goods Provision by National States," Comparative Political Studies, 49(10): 1341-1371.
Soss, Joe, and Schram, Sanford. 2007. “A Public Transformed? Welfare Reform as Policy Feedback,” American Political Science Review101(1), 111-127.
Soss, Joe, Richard Fording, and Sanford F. Schram. 2008. “The Color of Devolution: Race, Federalism, and the Politics of Social Control,” The American Journal of Political Science, 52(3): 536-553.
Schram, Sanford, Joe Soss, Richard Fording, and Linda Houser. 2009. "Deciding to Discipline: Race, Politics, and Punishment at the Front Lines of Welfare Reform," American Sociological Review, 74(3): 398-422.
Soss, Joe., Richard Fording, and Sanford Schram. 2011. “The Organization of Discipline: From Performance Management to Perversity and Punishment,” Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory21(2): 203-232.
Steele, Liza G. 2016. "Ethnic Diversity and Support for Redistributive Social Policies," Social Forces, 94(4): 1439-1481.
Tarman, Christopher and David Sears. 2005. “The Conceptualization and Measurement of Symbolic Racism,” The Journal of Politics, 67(3): 731–761.
Taylor, Marylee C.  1998. “How White Attitudes Vary with the Racial Composition of Local Populations: Numbers Count,” American Sociological Review, 63(4): 512-535.
Weber, Christopher R., Howard Lavine, Leonie Huddy, and Christopher M. Federico. 2014. “Placing Racial Stereotypes in Context: Social Desirability and the Politics of Racial Hostility,” The American Journal of Political Science, 58(1): 63–78.
White, Ismail K. 2007. “When Race Matters and When It Doesn’t: Racial Group Differences in Response to Racial Cues,” The American Political Science Review, 101(2).
Wood, Geof and Ian Gough. 2006. “A Comparative Welfare Regime Approach to Global Social Policy,” World Development, 34(10). 

Yörük, Erdem. 2012. “Welfare Provision as Political Containment: The Politics of Social Assistance and the Kurdish Conflict in Turkey.” Politics & Society40(4): 517–547.
Yörük, Erdem. "Shifting forms of Turkish State Paternalism toward the Kurds: social assistance as benevolent control," Dialectical Anthropology, 37(1): 153-58.

Thursday, January 10, 2019

Semi-Authoritarianism in American Political Thought

Introduction
         Academics in the United States are deeply divided over the historical nature of American political culture. In the 1950’s and 1960’s, the dominant theory was that America was born as a democratic and a capitalist society without a feudal past and that a liberal consensus has continued to maintain a grip on the culture all the way till the present day (See Hartz, 1955; Lipset, 1996). According to Louis Hartz, “One of the central characteristics of a non-feudal society is that it lacks a genuine revolutionary tradition, the tradition which Europe has been linked with the Puritan and French revolutions: that it is ‘born equal,’ as Tocqueville said.” (Hartz, 5) From this perspective, America has never had social classes nor was there ever an aristocracy to overthrow; therefore, its Revolution wasn’t really a social revolution in the vain of what happened in France in 1789 or Russia in 1917. However, since the late 1960’s, the liberal consensus has been challenged on a number of fronts by a plethora of academics (Rodgers, 1992). One of the most notable scholars is the historian Gordon Wood (See Wood, 1969 and 1991). In several books, most notably The Radicalism of the American Revolution and The Creation of the American Republic: 1776-1787, he not only questions the notion that America was born as a Lockean polity but attempts to place the American Revolution at the center of critical social and economic changes in world history such as the Enlightenment and the Commercial Revolution. According to Wood, the country first transformed from a society of monarchial patronage and aristocratic hierarchy to one of Republican civic virtue and enlightened paternalism throughout the course of the eighteenth century; following the Revolution, the country then transformed into a democratic society that promoted the values of equality, capitalism, and pluralism. Only by the early nineteenth century did America become the liberal, middle class polity so eloquently described in Alexis De Tocqueville’s classic work Democracy in America (De Tocqueville, 1966). From Wood’s perspective, America’s revolution was a critical event in its history and a source of massive socioeconomic change that parallels the French and Russian Revolutions in importance. 
         In light of these contrasting perspectives, does Wood or Hartz offer a better conceptualization of the evolution of American political culture? Or are there flaws with both of their theories? Furthermore, is Gordon Wood’s characterization of the social conditions before and after the American Revolution an accurate assessment of American history and the revolution’s impact on the culture? In more simple terms, was America’s revolution really a social revolution that caused the country’s transition from a republican to a democratic society, or was it a conservative political movement that aimed to restore the principles of government that had already existed since the founding of the Thirteen Colonies? 
         There are several reasons why it is important to address these questions beyond the motive of mere academic curiosity. Hartz’s theory implies that America’s political culture is relatively static. Political scientists that ascribe to the liberal consensus have used the theory to provide answers to controversial debates in the field of American political science. This includes questions over why the American public is staunchly capitalist, why the country has a weak welfare state in comparison with Europe, or why the country has problems with gun violence (Lipset, 1996). For Hartz, Americans are incapable of seeing beyond their Lockean liberal sensibilities. However, authors such as Gordon Wood and David Greenstone have questioned this perception of American political culture. They have pointed out the existence of past ideological rifts such as ones that divided loyalists and patriots during the Revolution or the North and the South during the Civil War (Wood, 1991; Greenstone, 1993). According to these authors, this shows that America’s political culture is dynamic. From this perspective, the country is capable of experiencing far more radical ideological change than authors such as Louis Hartz have been willing to admit. This has repercussions for America’s future. 
         In order to address this debate, I will first conduct a literature review of important writings in American political thought. These works will include defenders of the Lockean consensus such as Louis Hartz, Alexis De Tocqueville, and Seymour Lipset, and it will also include critiques of it by academics such as Gordon Wood, Bernard Bailyn, J.G.A. Pollock, Sean Wilentz, Sacvan Bercovitch, and J. David Greenstone. After outlining the positions of authors from the different schools of thought, I will then analyze the strengths and weaknesses of their arguments by clearly outlining how we should define and measure a country’s political culture. It is my contention that a political culture should be defined by the values that dominate a society during a period of time. It is not good enough to cherry pick quotes from authors in the past; instead, we should analyze whether those ideas were dominant in society. It is the structure of the political regime tells us what ideas were dominant or suppressed at various points in history. For example, abolitionism existed as a political movement in late eighteenth century America, but it is not until the 1850’s and 1860’s that those ideas become widespread to the point where they significantly influenced the political system. By clearly defining America’s regime at various points in its history, we can than analyze how the country’s political culture evolved. Works written by the founding fathers such as the Declaration of Independence, Common Sense, the Constitution, and the Federalist Papers will be scrutinized as will secondary sources that discuss the political thought of the eighteenth and early nineteenth century. After doing this, I can then assess the validity of Hartz’s and Wood’s claims. 
         As will be shown in this paper, both the liberalism of Hartz and republicanism of Wood mischaracterize American political thought. While Gordon Wood successfully demonstrates the illiberal nature of many aspects of political thought in colonial America and the liberal reforms that followed the American revolution, he fails to address the persistence of illiberal ideals into the nineteenth and twentieth centuries as well as the continuation of conflict between conservatives supporting the status quo and liberal reformers. It is my contention that early American political thought should be described as semi-authoritarian in that embraced the liberal ideals of John Locke from the very beginning but only applied those ideals to white male landowners. Illiberal authoritarian rhetoric was used to justify the exclusion of certain groups from the political process—racial minorities, the poor, women, and Native Americans. Gordon Wood’s Republicanism only addresses the exclusion of landless whites from the political system during the formative years of American independence and neglects the rhetoric of racism, patriarchy, and xenophobia that has been used to exclude other groups in society in the two centuries that followed. In the 1830’s, America was only a liberal society for white males as other groups were excluded from the democratic political system and the bountiful wealth of land and resources in the West. From this perspective, the persistence of capitalist rhetoric and America’s weak welfare state is not a product of the entrenchment of liberal political values since the country’s founding but a product of wealthy whites resisting the redistribution of wealth to poorer minorities disadvantaged by centuries of oppression. Only since the civil rights movement of the 1950’s and 1960’s has America’s political culture truly begun to approach the liberal democratic ideal espoused by Louis Hartz although progressive reforms have been consistently met with resistance by conservative forces blocking changes that would make America a more inclusive society. While these social cleavages in the United States may be different from the class conflict Europe experienced in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, this does not mean America’s political thought has been characterized by a consensus. The violence of the Civil War and the Civil Rights Movement tells a different story.
          
The Liberal Consensus
         The liberal consensus theory has its origins with writings of the French academic Alexis De Tocqueville. In 1831, he traveled to America for nine months and took notes while visiting the country. Upon returning home, he used those observations and historical documents to write the book Democracy in America. The main purpose of the research was to compare the political systems of Europe with the United States and understand the different processes of democratization that were happening on each side of the Atlantic. De Tocqueville notes that 
The emigrants who colonized America at the beginning of the seventeenth century in some way separated the principle of democracy from all those other principles against which they contended when living in the heart of the old European societies, and transplanted that principle only on the shores of the New World. It could there grow in freedom…and develop peacefully within the law. (De Tocqueville, 18)

In other words, America was born a liberal democracy as the country never experienced a period of feudalism like what transpired in Europe. Consequently, the United States did not require a social revolution to destroy the privileges of the aristocracy and the Catholic Church like what happened in France in 1789. Instead, the nation was populated mainly by a diverse group of middle class Protestants seeking land and opportunity in the New World. They brought with them a spirit of egalitarianism in the culture that did not exist to the same extant anywhere in the Old World. Since America was thousands of miles away from Europe, the country never had to seriously worry about outside invaders disrupting this experiment in democratic governance. While summing up his experiences, De Tocqueville notes “No novelty in the United States struck me more vividly during my stay there than the equality of conditions. (De Tocqueville, 1)” This does not mean that De Tocqueville is claiming that there were no forms of social hierarchy in America. For example, he discusses the political oppression of Native Americans and the negative ramifications of slavery on the political economy in the South (De Tocqueville, 316-407). Nevertheless, De Tocqueville asserts that American society, when looked at as a whole, was far more liberal, egalitarian, and middle class in comparison with states in Western Europe. By the 1830’s, America had already expanded suffrage to almost all white male adults, which was much earlier than in any European state. From De Tocqueville’s ideas was born the notion that a liberal consensus has dominated American political life since its foundations.
         A great number of historians, political scientists, economists, philosophers, and novelists have built upon De Tocqueville’s ideas to explain many of the peculiarities—trivial and important—in American political life. One of the most notable academics in this tradition is the philosopher Louis Hartz, who wrote a book titled The Liberal Tradition in Americain 1955 (Hartz, 1955). According to Hartz, political thought in America was dominated by the ideas that were best articulated by the seventeenth-century English philosopher John Locke. In Locke’s work The Second Treatise on Government, he argues that 
To understand political power right, and derive from its original, we must consider what state all men are naturally in, and that is a state of perfect freedom to order their actions, and dispose of their possessions, and persons as they think fit within the bounds of the Law of Nature, without asking leave or depending on the will of any other man. A state also of equality wherein all of the power and jurisdiction is reciprocal. (Locke, 4)

From the Lockean perspective, all men are naturally born equal and free, and it is monarchies that corrupt the natural order of the world. If men are given their civil liberties, political rights, a liberal education, and the freedom to own their own land, they will be in a better position to meet their potential as human beings. Locke was making these arguments in the context of late seventeenth-century English society when there were intense political debates between conservative Tories and liberal Whigs. English Conservatives such as Robert Filmer supported a strong monarchy, a centralized church order, mercantilism, and aristocratic privileges. Liberal Whigs like Locke preferred a strong parliament, voting rights for the middle class, free trade, and a protestant ethic of hard work and individual interpretation of the Bible. England was torn apart politically and socially by the divide between the aristocracy and the growing urban middle class, which culminated in the English Civil War from 1642 to 1651 and the Glorious Revolution in 1688. According to Hartz, economic and religious migrants that fled persecution in Europe and traveled to America in the seventeenth century took this Lockean perspective with them and left the traditional conservative political ideals behind them in the Old World. These Lockean ideals are encapsulated in the words of Thomas Jefferson in the Declaration of Independence: 
We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty, and the pursuit of Happiness.—That to secure the rights, Governments are instituted among Men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed,--That whenever any Form of Government becomes destructive of these ends, it is the Right of the People to alter to abolish it, and to institute new Government, laying its foundations on such principles and organizing its powers in such form, as to them shall seem most likely to effect their Safety and Happiness. (Jefferson, 1776)

We also find these Lockian ideals within the Bill of Rights of the constitution, which limits the power of the federal government and guarantees freedom of speech, freedom of assembly, freedom of religion, and due process for all citizens. According to proponents of the liberal consensus, these ideals were established in the culture from the very beginning. In the New World, upstarts with economic and political ambition faced no resistance from an aristocratic class of conservatives. Instead, migrants found greater opportunities to own land and participate in politics free of the social hierarchies that once dominated the lives of their ancestors. They were able to create Locke’s political vision in the American wilderness. 
         For Hartz, this had several consequences for American political life. Since Americans never have been seriously exposed to an ideology that significantly differed from liberalism, they never had to defend their Lockean principles. Consequently, capitalism, small government, and pluralistic democracy became unquestioned dogmas within the culture. This has made it difficult for political parties that deviate from the consensus to gain acceptance with the public. For example, Federalists in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century struggled to convince the population of the need for a strong federal government and the importance of limiting seats in the legislature to gentlemen of high standing. Instead, the Jeffersonian Democrat’s emphasis on political equality and decentralized government won the day. Consequently, the Federalists faded into obscurity while the Democratic Party rose to prominence in the early 1800’s. The Whigs, who succeeded the Federalists as a political party in the 1830’s, also struggled electorally until they started to adopt the rhetoric and political strategies of the Democrats. 
         This trend applies to other epochs in America history. In the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries when the country was rapidly industrializing, populists and socialist movements calling for the redistribution of wealth and labor rights struggled to gain ground in America. As stated by Hartz: 
“For swallowing up both peasantry and proletariat into the ‘petit bourgeoisie’ scheme, America created two unusual effects. It prevented socialism from challenging its Liberal Reform in any effective way, and at the same time it enslaved its Liberal Reform to the Alger dream of democratic capitalism. (Hartz, 228)” 

In other words, the American working class is too heterogeneous and mobile to unite under a socialist program, and its population is distrustful of state intervention in the economy. As a result, the country has never had a true working class movement or strong national labor unions. It is true that progressives in the early twentieth century and supporters of the New Deal in the 1930’s did find some success in passing laws that involved regulation of the marketplace and the creation of welfare programs, but they had to use the language of capitalism to justify their policies. To win elections, America’s political parties have had to stay close ideologically to the liberal consensus lest they become irrelevant.
         This liberal consensus has not only affected the fortunes of interest groups and political parties but the freedom of American civil society in general. According to Hartz, Americans are so dogmatically liberal that there is a tendency for people to be incredibly intolerant of any ideas that are outside the established norm. De Tocqueville noticed this trend as well, claiming that “In America the majority has enclosed thought within a formidable fence. A writer is free inside that area, but woe to the man who goes beyond it. (De Tocqueville, 255)” It is usually not the state that persecutes free thought in America but the popular majority who use intimidation and condemnation to banish violators from the public sphere. For Hartz, this explains why Americans became far more fearful of the communist threat in the 1950’s than their Western European counterparts even though there were far fewer communists in the United States. Writing his work at the height of McCarthyism, Hartz knew only too well the paranoid nature of the American public, who could lash out at ideological minorities during a moment of crisis. The country has had several episodes of mass hysteria and panic over the perceived threat from ideological influences that were outside the norms of the political culture. 
         This cultural trend has had other interesting consequences for American political life. Hartz notes that “the American historian at practically every stage has functioned quite inside the nation: he has tended to be an erudite reflection of the limited social perspectives of the average American himself. (Hartz, 29)” In other words, average Americans and even academics are generally ignorant of foreign philosophies. Consequently, this has made them prone to mislabeling their political opponents. For example, Jeffersonian Democrats in the early 1800’s often referred to their Federalist opponents as aristocrats in a derogatory manner. However, the great majority of Federalists would not have been labeled with such a designation in Europe. While Federalists were generally wealthy, they usually had to labor to maintain their standard of living. For example, John Adams and Alexander Hamilton both had law practices. In contrast, real aristocrats in Europe had large enough land holdings where they could live off the rents from their inherited property and enjoy lives of leisure. Since the average size of landownership in America was smaller and more equitable, most American landowners had to work for a living. This did not stop Democrats from mislabeling their Federalist opponents. 
         We see this trend of mislabeling political adversaries in other eras in American history. For example, progressives in the early to mid- twentieth century that supported programs like the New Deal have often been mislabeled as socialists. This is strange from the European perspective as they see both the Democratic and Republican Parties as being staunchly capitalist. America’s welfare state is far more limited than most states in continental Europe. In more recent history, past Democratic presidents such as Bill Clinton and Barrack Obama regularly promoted free trade agreements and the neoliberal Washington Consensus. This has not stopped their domestic opponents from labeling them as radical leftists. For this reason, an academic has to be careful not to always take historical figures literally when analyzing primary documents on American political thought. Exaggeration and political misrepresentation is common in a society ignorant of philosophies outside the established dogma and paranoid of the creeping influences of foreign ideologies. 
         The liberal consensus theory continues to have an impact on the ideas of political scientists up until the present day. One of the more recent works on the subject is Seymour Lipset’s American Exceptionalism: A Double Edged Sword (Lipset, 1996). According Lipset, the hegemonic domination of liberal political thought has made America exceptional in both positive and negative ways.  By way of analyzing historical documents, World Values Survey data from 1980 and 1990, and economic statistics, he shows how the United States drastically differs from Western Europe, Canada, and Japan. For example, America has an unusually weak welfare state in comparison with other developed countries, and Americans are more likely to believe in the efficacy of free markets over state intervention in the economy. In contrast, the average European is more likely to be believe the poor are deserving of welfare, and European governments are more likely to redistribute wealth to the bottom quartile. In addition, Americans tend to uphold the values of self-help and individualism whereas Europeans, Canadians, and the Japanese tend to emphasize communal solidarity. Moreover, freer markets in America have arguably encouraged more creativity, innovation, and private investments in higher education, which might explain why the country has the world’s highest GDP. However, European states have better measurements on other economic indicators like economic equality and life expectancy. Since Americans tend to believe in weak government and individualism, they also have a greater tendency to own guns, break the law, and commit acts of violence. Americans are less bound to the rules of the state than in Europe. It is for these reasons that Lipset calls American exceptionalism a double-edged sword. 
         Furthermore, Lipset shows how Americans are unusually devoted to religion in comparison with other developed countries. In Europe, most states witnessed bloody revolutions and the rise of far left socialist and communist movements throughout the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. The power of the Catholic Church was severely weakened through political violence. Since the Church was seen as impediment to progress by many leftists due to the institution’s alliance with the aristocracy and monarchy, religiosity declined among the middle and working classes. However, America was founded by Protestants fleeing persecution. The evangelical protestant emphasis on hard work, individual liberty, and the prosperity gospel fit in well with America’s democratic and capitalist consensus, so religion and modernity were able to develop in tandem with one another in the United States. Lipset’s analysis of survey data reveals that in comparison with Europeans, Americans are more likely believe in God and support traditional Christian values such as pro-life policies, marriage between a man and a women, and prayer in public schools.  Since the state is far weaker in America, protestant churches became the glue that held modern society together. De Tocqueville agreed with this sentiment in the 1830’s: 
Most of English America was peopled by men who, having shaken off the pope’s authority, acknowledged no other religious supremacy; they there brought to the New World a Christianity which I can only describe as democratic and republican; this fact singularly favored the establishment of a temporal republic and democracy. From the start politics and religion agreed, and they have not since ceased to do so. (De Tocqueville, 288) 

America’s Protestant ethos is a critical aspect of the country’s national identity and part of what makes the nation stand out from the rest of the developed world.
         Lipset does note that there are some exceptions to these general trends in America. Minorities such as African Americans and Jews tend to espouse views that are more left wing on the welfare state due to their unique histories. African Americans suffered under several centuries of slavery and then a century of Jim Crow segregation. Under Jim Crow, local governments dominated by conservative whites discriminated against blacks. By the 1960’s, African Americans were twelve times poorer than the average white family. Consequently, the black community is more likely to support welfare provisions to the poor and a stronger federal government to prevent discrimination at the local level. While Jews tend to be much wealthier than whites due to their particular history as European migrants, they also suffered from discrimination in Europe before immigrating to the United States. Consequently, they have more sympathy than white Protestants for the plight of the poor and minorities. There are other groups that fall outside of the common trend such as left-wing academics. However, these minority trends remain exceptions to the rule in America. Hartz and De Tocqueville use the same reasoning as Lipset. While slavery was a horrible episode in American history, it was experienced by a minority of the population whereas feudalism in Europe subjected most of the population to authoritarian rule prior to the nineteenth century. This fomented class consciousness on the European continent whereas America’s history of immigration and ethnic diversity prevented the lower classes from forming a sense of class solidarity.

 Opponents of Liberalism: The Republican Challenge
         While the liberal consensus continues to have a lot of support among academics today, significant challenges to this theory emerged in the late 1960’s. In the prior two decades, America experienced a cultural revolution, which witnessed protests movements calling for civil rights, women’s rights, gay rights, environmentalism, and an end to nuclear proliferation and the Vietnam War. Debates over these issues intensified throughout sixties as Americans clashed over the nature of their democracy and their national identity. In this politically divisive environment, many young scholars began questioning the liberal consensus on a number of fronts. Some academics claimed that America was not born as a liberal polity. Others attempted to provide evidence that the country was influenced by non-liberal ideologies at various points in its history. A lot of effort was focused on proving the existence of an alternative ideological trend in American political thought called republicanism, which is this ideal that good citizens should sacrifice their petty self-interests for the sake of the community. Sean Wilentz eloquently summarizes the tenants of the republican ethos in his book Chants Democratic:
As recovered by J.G.A. Pollock, this discourse (of Republicanism) rested largely on four interlocking concepts: first, that the ultimate goal of any political society should be the preservation of the public good, or commonwealth; second, that in order to maintain the commonwealth, the citizens of a republic had to be willing and able to exercise virtue, to subordinate private ends to the legislation of the public good when they conflicted; third, that in order to be virtuous, citizens had to be independent of the political will of other men, lest they lose sight of the common good; fourth, that in order to guard against the encroachments of would-be tyrants, citizens had to be active in politics to exercise their citizenship. (Wilentz, 14)

While liberalism emphasizes the importance of individual interest, self-help, and the pursuit of personal happiness, republicanism demands sacrificing one’s personal ambitions for the sake of the community. From the republican point of view, liberty is only possible if people remain vigilant citizens who struggle against vices in society. Those who think of the nation’s interests as opposed to their own desires possess civic virtue. Furthermore, republicanism promotes the ideal that only those who hold civic virtue should become leaders of the community. Therefore, politics should be limited to those who have the time and talent to understand the complex problems facing the whole nation and are dedicated to its cause. Unlike liberalism, which promotes equality and pluralism, republicanism assumes that some men have more virtue than others based on their talent, wealth, and/or education. Scholars in the republican tradition have argued that ideals such as nationalism, social solidarity, and civic virtue are all powerful currents within American political thought.
         While scholars of the liberal consensus trace the origin of American political culture to liberal English Whigs like John Locke, scholars of republicanism trace the roots of American political thought back to a diversity of different sources.  One important source is the writings of classical Roman Republican authors and statesmen such as Cicero and Cato. During the Renaissance and the Enlightenment, there was a revival of interest in the ideas and political systems of the classical civilizations of Greece and Rome. Scholars in Europe regularly learned Greek and Latin in universities, and many of the classics were translated into vernacular languages. Fascination with these older civilizations was not only mere academic curiosity; the Roman Republic served as an inspiration for enlightened reformers living at a time in continental Europe when absolute monarchies dominated the political landscape. Unlike these authoritarian systems, the Roman Republic had a government that divided power between the patricians, who were the elites in the military and the aristocracy, and the plebeians, who were the lower classes—thereby checking the ambitions of would-be tyrants. It was a system that encouraged male citizens to give up their personal interests by serving in the military and working for the greater good of the community. Citizens who served in the military were given land and the freedom to participate in politics. In the Federalist Papers—a famous collection of essays written by the founding fathers James Madison, John Jay, and Alexander Hamilton to promote the ratification of the American constitution—it is very clear that the Roman Republic served as inspiration for the construction of the new American government:
It is well known that in the Roman republic the legislative authority, in the last resort, resided for ages in two different political bodies not as branches of the same legislature, but as distinct and independent legislatures, in each of which an opposite interest prevailed: in one the patrician; in the other, the plebian. Many arguments might have been adduced to prove the unfitness of two such seemingly contradictory authorities, each having power to ANNUL or REPEAL the acts of the other. But a man would have been regarded as frantic who should have attempted at Rome to disprove their existence. It will be readily understood that I allude to the COMITIA CENTURIATA and the COMITIA TRIBUTA. The former, in which the people voted by centuries, was so arranged as to give a superiority to the patrician interest; in the latter, in which numbers prevailed, the plebian interest had an entire predominancy. And yet these two legislatures coexisted for ages, and the Roman republic attained to the utmost height of human greatness. (Hamilton, Federalist # )

For the framers of the constitution, Rome was proof that republics could not only function but thrive under certain circumstances.
         The Republics of Renaissance Italy were also an inspiration for the founding fathers. It was in Renaissance Italy during the fourteenth and fifteenth century that republicanism was first revived as a political system in Europe. Wealthy city states in northern Italy such as Florence and Venice adopted a system of government where power was divided between wealthy merchant families. Furthermore, citizens in these urban polities were encouraged to sacrifice their wealth, skills, and time to participate in civil society. Famous politicians and writers in Renaissance Italy such as Nicolo Machiavelli praised the values of civic humanism and republicanism while condemning the tyranny of monarchies on the European continent. Through civic participation, citizens could strengthen their community and serve as a check against corruption. While Machiavelli is better known for his defense of immoral behavior by politicians if it leads to positive public outcomes, he was also a defender of the republican values of mixed government. This is why the scholar J.G.A. Pollock, in his 1975 book The Machiavellian Moment, traces the origins of republican ideals in colonial America to Renaissance Italy. Machiavelli also provided advice to politicians in new republics on how to survive during moments of political instability, which made his ideas valuable to American politicians in the early years of the republic. Few founding fathers cited Machiavelli as much as John Adams, who mentioned him several times in his 1787 work In Defense of the Constitution (Adams, 1787). In this work, Adams analyzes the history of republicans from Ancient, Renaissance, and Enlightenment Europe in order to highlight the potential strengths and weaknesses of past republican systems of government. 
         The republican ideals of Enlightenment scholars of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries also had an impact on the founders. One of the most important examples is the French scholar Baron De Montesquieu, who believed that the ideal government was a republic that created a separation of powers between different factions of society. From this perspective, the best form of government was one that had the strength and cohesion of a monarchy but whose power was checked by both aristocratic elites and common citizens through republican institutions. Without checks, a king would act like a tyrant; however, if power is given to the whole populace unchecked, the poorly educated majority would abuse the educated minority. Montesquieu felt that the constitutional monarchy of Great Britain, which balanced the power of the King with that of the aristocracy and the urban middle class through the House of Lords and the House of Commons, was the best embodiment of these republican ideals. While the king enforced legislation, it was parliament that wrote the laws and controlled the purse string. This enabled men to participate in government, but it gave a disproportionate influence to those who owned land and had an education. From these republican ideals was born the notion that the ideal government should have a separation of powers between the legislative, executive, and judicial branches. In Federalist Paper Number 47, James Madison writes
In order to form correct ideas on this important subject, it will be proper to investigate the sense in which the preservation of liberty requires that the three great departments of power should be separate and distinct. The oracle who is always consulted and cited on this subject is the celebrated Montesquieu. (Madison, Federalist 47)

Clearly, John Locke’s philosophy was not the only set of ideals that influenced the founding fathers. Within the Federalist Papers, there are many instances where Alexander Hamilton, James Madison, and John Jay discuss the positive and negative attributes of past republics. The founders not only drew inspiration from these past republics but sought to avoid the weaknesses that led to their collapse:
A firm Union will be of the utmost moment to the peace and liberty of the States, as a barrier against domestic faction and insurrection. It is impossible to read the history of the petty republics of Greece and Italy without feeling sensations of horror and disgust at the distractions with which they were continually agitated, and at the rapid succession of revolutions by which they were kept in a state of perpetual vibration between the extremes of tyranny and anarchy. (Hamilton, Federalist #9)

While they detested the semi-authoritarian nature and militaristic ambitions of some of these republics, they found utility in these systems in terms of the way they balanced political power to check the ambitions of individuals. By having checks and balances, you could create a political system that would work for the good of the public. 
         While some scholars have focused on these secular origins of civic virtue and republicanism, other academics have highlighted the influence of Protestantism on the development of America’s republican values. For example, Sacvan Bercovitch, in his 1978 book The American Jeremiad, examines the influence of Puritan thought on American national identity (Bercovitch, 1978). To do this, he analyzes the Jeremiads or sermons of preachers in the colonial era and the impact these sermons had on political discourse. Jeremiads were sermons that condemned the evils and vices of this world while urging Christians to seek redemption. For those Puritan preachers that traveled to New England in the seventeenth century, they saw an opportunity for redemption by establishing a New Jerusalem—a City on Hill—that would be shinning beacon of Christian values for the rest of the world to emulate. While European preachers tended to have a more pessimistic view of the world and saw paradise as existing in the next life, the American Jeremiads of seventeenth century New England emphasized the creation of paradise in this life. It was a contradictory message that was at once pessimistic about present conditions but optimistic about the potential for progress in the future. Like past prophets such as Jeremiah, it was the duty or errand of Puritans to seek redemption for their past sins, conquer the wilderness, and create a Godly community based on virtue in preparation for the rapture. During moments of crisis, preachers in America use these Jeremiads as calls for renewal and the establishment of a virtuous community.
         In many ways, Puritanism presents a dilemma for promoters of the liberal consensus. The Puritans who settled in New England in the seventeenth century initially created protestant theocracies in the New World. These theocratic communities were a far cry from the liberal society describe by De Tocqueville in the 1830’s.  In defense of the liberal consensus, scholars such as Louis Hartz have argued that Puritanism was a brief episode in America’s early history and thus inconsequential (Hartz, 1955). By the early eighteenth century, Puritanism would disappear as economic migrants interested in the pursuit of wealth and happiness would flood into the North East. This led to the creation of a Yankee merchant culture in New England. By the early 1700’s, the first Great Awakening spread across America, and Methodist and Baptist ideals came to dominant American religious values. These new forms of Protestant Christianity emphasized one’s individual connection with God and rejected the strict doctrines of predestination and theocracy emphasized by Puritans. 
         However, Bercovitch argues that Puritan ideals had a long term impact on the political culture (Bercovitch, 1978). While Puritan communities did eventually disappear, their ideas influenced the preachers of the Great Awakening as well as the political thought of the Founding Fathers. It was originally the Puritan mission in New England to establish an exemplary city on a hill, but it became America’s mission to establish a virtuous society by the time of the revolution. What was once purely a religious sermon became a political sermon used by politicians during moments of crisis to call for national action to confront a crisis. For example, preachers during the American Revolution used the Jeremiad to call for revolution against the British and the establishment of a new polity. According to Bercovitch:
By all accounts, the Jeremiad played a central role in the war of independence, and the war in turn confirmed the Jeremiad as a national ritual. The Whig sermons and tracts express a rite of passage into nation-hood, an official coming-of-age ceremony, which had long been in rehearsal (Bercovitch, 132). 

For many protestant preachers, it was God’s providence that Americans would establish a virtuous nation and eliminate the vices of the British Empire. Even an atheist such as Thomas Paine understood the power of these ideas in the American subconscious. In his famous pamphlet Common Sense, he uses a concept called Hebraic Republicanism as one of his justifications for revolution against the British monarchy:
Near three thousand years passed away, from the Mosaic account of creation, till the Jews under a national delusion requested a king. Till then their form of government (except in extraordinary cases where the almighty interposed) was a kind of republic, administered by a judge and the elders of the tribes. Kings they had none, and it was sinful to acknowledge any being under that title except the Lord of Hosts (Paine, 2013).

In other words, Paine is saying that the bible promotes republicanism and condemns monarchy. Over and over again, Protestants would also use this type of language to promote social solidarity, national progress, and republican values. For example, we find this trend in the rhetoric of manifest destiny, which justified America’s westward expansion as a means to spread the country’s Christian virtue across the continent. From this perspective, American capitalism and economic growth are not the selfish motives of atomistic individuals seeking a fortune but instead exemplify the virtuous hard work of citizens building a better civilization in the New World. This rhetoric is still used in the present era. President Reagan, in his quarrels with the Soviet Union, often spoke of America as a city on hill—a beacon of freedom, progress and Christian moral values that could serve as an example for the rest of the world. From Bercovitch’s perspective, Puritan ideas became the foundations of American nationalism in the young republic. Other scholars have made similar claims. For example, the academic Josua Fienstag reinterprets the very symbol of the liberal consensus—the ideas of John Locke—by showing how we can find notions of republicanism and civic virtue in Locke’s conception of the Protestant Ethic in some of his writings (Fienstag, 1996).
         While republicanism has been used by scholars as a means for critiquing the liberal consensus, there is a lot of diversity among those who support the republican alternative and a lack of consensus on the precise definition of the concept. According to the political scientist Don Herzog:
Those championing republicanism, virtue, and community today also need to explain in some sort of detail…what sort of politics they are offering. Too much time has been spent assaulting liberalism, too little articulating an alternative in any detail. (Herzog, 1986)

While scholars of the liberal consensus present a more coherent summary of American political thought, republicanism has produced many contradictions. There is a lack of agreement in terms of where these ideas originate and what influence they have had on the culture. Furthermore, some scholars contend that republican values have existed side-by-side with liberal ideals while others argue that liberalism has had no real influence on the culture at all. To make sense of the republican literature, some scholars have attempted to classify the different strands of thought. One of those academics is the historian Daniel Rodgers, who breaks down the republican tradition into two major trends: Harvard Republicanism and St. Louis Republicanism (Rodgers, 1992). To understand Gordon Wood’s position, it is worthwhile to discuss the differences between each faction.
         The first school of thought, Harvard Republicanism, is best exemplified by the works of historians such as Bernard Bailyn, Jane Garrett, and Gordon Wood. According to these scholars, traditional values such as monarchy, aristocracy, dependency, and patriarchy initially dominated political life in the thirteen colonies, but those values were gradually undermined by the ideals of republicanism, which were becoming increasingly popular among the growing middle class. During the course of the revolution, Americans became swept up by republican ideals such as civic virtue, patriotism, and self-sacrifice. As the problems in the post-revolutionary period of the 1780’s mounted, the founding fathers suppressed the popular enthusiasm of the population for liberal democracy by establishing a new constitution in 1787 that placed limits on the power of the masses and created a federal republic. The new constitution created a stronger central government and limited the popular vote through the creation of an upper house in the legislature and an electoral college in the vote for the presidency. States continued to restrict voting rights to while males who owned property. According to the Harvard Republican scholars, these republican values did not dominate the political culture for very long. In the aftermath of the revolution, republican values of patriotism and civic humanism faded and gave way to a liberalism that emphasized the middle class values of self-interest, pluralism, democracy, and capitalism. Gradually, voting rights were expanded to include groups excluded from the system. In the Harvard School of thought, Republicanism is more than an ideological trend that emphasizes civic virtue; it is also a description of the political regime that existed during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries.
         To provide substance to their theory, Harvard republican scholars have found examples of civic virtue and other non-Lockean ideas in the writings of supporters of the American Revolution. For example, Bernard Bailyn and Jane Garett, in their edited book Pamphlets of the American Revolution: 1750-1776, show how pamphleteers during the American Revolution such as John Dickinson and Thomas Paine promoted republicanism and condemned the English monarchy and aristocracy (Bailyn and Garett, 1965). These patriots called upon their fellow citizens to risk their lives for to establish a republic where virtuous citizens representing the common good would run the government instead of a monarchy that only had its self interest in mind. In the following quote, Thomas Paine, in his famous pamphlet Common Sense, eloquently promotes republican values exemplified by the British House of Commons while condemning the authoritarian nature of the monarchy and the House of Lords:
If we will suffer ourselves to examine the component parts of the English constitution we shall find them to be the base remains of two ancient tyrannies compounded with some new republican materials: First, the remains of monarchial tyranny in the person of the king. Secondly, the remains of aristocratical tyranny in the persons of the peers. Thirdly, the new republican materials in the persons of the commons, on whose virtue depends the freedom of England. (Paine, 7)

In Common Sense, Paine used both secular arguments derived from European history and religious arguments derived from the Old Testament of the Bible to defend the efficacy of republicanism and criticize the moral vices of absolute monarchies. Baine and Garrett also show how these pamphleteers were genuinely opposed to what they saw as tyranny of the British Empire. While America did have elected legislatures in the colonial period, power in colonial governments was heavily influenced by royally appointed governments and voting rights were heavily restricted to white male land owners. From this perspective, America was not a democracy prior to 1776 but a society that had a mix of monarchial, aristocratic, and republican values. 
         According to these scholars, republicanism also influenced the political ideas of the Founding Fathers. While anti-federalists such as Patrick Henry preached the Lockean values of equality, civil rights, and small government, Federalists tended to espouse republican ideals of enlightened paternalism and civic virtue. In 1790, John Adams wrote an essay called Discourses on Davila where he defends the necessity of virtue and the need for society to have men of high standing become leaders in government and society (Adams, 1790). In the essay, he condemns the French revolutionaries for attempting to destroy all forms of hierarchy in society and political order, and he claims that this goes against human nature. He extols Americans for allowing those with reason and virtue to create a well-ordered society and government:
Americans! Rejoice, that from your experience you have learned wisdom; and instead of whimsical and fantastic projects, you have adopted a promising essay towards a well-ordered government. Instead of following any foreign example, to return to the legislation of confusion, contemplate the means of restoring decency, honesty, and order in society, by preserving and completing, if anything should be found necessary to complete the balance of government. In a well-balanced government, reason, conscience, truth, and virtue, must be respected by all parties, and exerted for the public good. (Adams, 300)

Adams is not claiming that this societal or political order should be based on antiquated notions of monarchy or aristocracy; instead, those with power should be gentlemen of talent, education, and civic virtue. For Adams, there is nothing wrong with recognizing certain men as superior. In fact, throughout the colonial period and in the half century after independence, only white males that owned property could vote in most states. It was not until 1856 that the last state eliminated property requirements for voting. Politicians who defended these property requirements often used similar republican arguments in their defense of limiting suffrage. Simply put, from their perspective, a landless man without education was not good enough to participate in politics.
         Within the 1787 constitution, republican scholars such as Gordon Wood have also found plenty of evidence for the existence of republican values. Federalists wanted to design a constitution that gave elites a disproportional influence on the government and protected the interests of the minority in the process. For example, representatives in the House were and continue to be directly voted in by their constituents, but Senators were initially chosen indirectly by state legislatures until the early twentieth century. This ensured that these men would come from a class of wealthy elites. The results had their desired effect. Even De Tocqueville notes the different quality of men that occupied the Senate versus those that occupied the House: 
When one enters the House of Representatives at Washington, one is struck by the vulgar demeanor of the great assembly. One can often look in vain for a single famous man…In a country where education is spread almost universally, it is said that the people’s representatives do not always know how write correctly. A couple paces away is the entrance to the Senate, whose narrow precincts contain a large proportion of the famous men of America…They are eloquent advocates, distinguished generals, wise magistrate, and noted statesmen. (De Tocqueville, 1966)

While the House of Representatives contains the type of politicians that personified a society that emphasized equality, the Senate was a personification of republican values. This characterization of the two houses arguably still applies today. The founders believed in the need for the popular majority to influence the new government, but they wanted to place checks on the majority. Furthermore, the founders also created a strong executive branch with a president this is still chosen indirectly through an electoral college and not by the majority vote of the population. The Supreme Court has also acted as an enlightened check against the will of the majority. While the framers of the constitution did not initially intend for the courts to play this role, the 1803 Supreme Court case Marbury vs. Madison established judicial review, which has allowed the courts to strike down laws as unconstitutional when a case is brought forth by private citizens. In other words, a group of well-educated judges chosen by an indirectly elected president have the ability to alter or abolish laws passed by a popular assembly. Even Louis Hartz argues that lawyers and judges have acted as a pseudo aristocracy in America by protecting the rule of law and holding back the popular enthusiasm of the majority of citizens. The Bill of Rights, which were supported by the anti-federalists, was only added to the constitution late in the process of ratifying the document to appease anti-federalist opponents of these republican values.  
         Promotors of the Harvard School of Republicanism also show how Federalists were also opposed to the political influence of special interests and political parties. This clashes with the Lockean ideal that individuals should pursue their personal goals. Many federalists saw political parties and special interests as a form of vice and a danger to the unity of the new republic. How could parties and other groups with special interests govern when they are not interested in the good of the whole community? James Madison, in the Federalist Paper number ten, argues:
Among the numerous advantages promised by a well constructed Union, none deserves to be more accurately developed than its tendency to break and control the violence of faction. The friend of popular governments never finds himself so much alarmed for their character and fate, as when he contemplates their propensity to this dangerous vice. He will not fail, therefore, to set a due value on any plan which, without violating the principles to which he is attached, provides a proper cure for it. The instability, injustice, and confusion introduced into the public councils, have, in truth, been the mortal diseases under which popular governments have everywhere perished. (Madison, Federalist Paper #10)

From the Federalist perspective, the duty of a congressmen was not to serve the constituents from their district or the interests of their political party but the entire nation. According to Republican scholars, these ideals dominated the political culture in the late eighteenth century.
         Nevertheless, scholars of the Harvard School of thought also think that republicanism faded away by the early nineteenth century (Wood, 1991). Many of the fears of the founding fathers—specifically, those of the federalist persuasion—were eventually realized in the decades following the revolution. By the 1820’s, most states had removed property qualifications from voting as a result of popular pressure from below as the country grew economically and geographically. To whip up support from these new voters, the Democratic Party, under the leadership of Andrew Jackson and Martin Van Buren, created a clientelistic party machine where promises of favors and jobs in the federal bureaucracy were used in exchange for political support. This strategy was successful and led to Andrew Jackson’s victory as president in 1828 and the creation of the spoils system. The Whigs, the successors to the Federalists, eventually emulated the same party structure. By this time period, many congressmen saw it as their duty to bring home as much pork—i.e., federal spending—as possible to their home districts and not to represent the interests of the whole nation. While the Constitution would remain as remnant of a time when republican values dominated American politics and would continue to influence the American political system, many scholars of republicanism such as Gordon Wood argue that these values faded away in the culture as liberalism took hold of the population. From this vantage point, the founders are considered a special generation within American history. 
         Scholars from the school of thought of St. Louis Republicanism have a different perspective on republican ideology. While Bailyn and Wood sees republicanism as fading away after the Revolution, St. Louis Republicans like J.G.A. Pollock and Sean Wilentz see the ideology as remerging in cycles during moments of crisis in the country (Wilentz, 2004). When troubled times like an economic depression or a war emerge, American political thinkers have a tendency to look back to the founding fathers for guidance and inspiration. Many have used their example to call for national unity, communal solidarity, and patriotic self-sacrifice against domestic challenges and foreign threats. For example, Abraham Lincoln, in speech given on January 27, 1838 in Springfield, Illinois, criticized the problems of mob violence and vigilante justice caused by proponents and opponents of slavery throughout the country by using the language of republicanism:
The question recurs “How shall we fortify against it?” The answer is simple. Let every American, every lover of liberty, every well wisher to his posterity, swear by the blood of the Revolution, never to violate in the least particular, the laws of the country; and never to tolerate their violation by others. As the patriots of seventy-six did to support the Declaration of Independence, so to the support of the Constitution and laws, let every American pledge his life, his property, and his sacred honor (Hamilton, Federalist #9).

From the St. Louis perspective, republicanism isn’t just a stage in America’s development from a traditional monarchial society to a liberal polity but a cultural trend that reemerges during moments of national self-doubt. 
         Since St. Louis Republicanism has a much looser definition of the concept, it has been used by scholars to describe a great diversity of ideological trends in American history. For example, some scholars of republicanism have searched for these values in the working class and labor movements of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries (Wilentz, 2004). Industrialization brought with it rapid changes including economic growth, urbanization, and a growing wealth gap between rich and poor. Capitalism has also led to a periods of booms and busts throughout the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. For workers living in growing American cities, the rough working and living conditions often led labor movements calling for unionization and worker solidarity. The existence of socialist ideals in the history of American political thought arguably contradicts one of the basic tenets of the liberal consensus. Several authors have used republicanism to explain the origins of these socialist ideals. For example, Sean Wilentz in the book Chants Democratic, chooses to focus on the formation of a working class movement in New York City from the late eighteenth to the middle of the nineteenth century. The formation of organizations such as the Working Man’s Party and the General Trades Union present examples of artisans and industrial workers engaging in solidarity by giving up their private interests for the good of their social class. In his analysis, he showed how radical thinkers such as Robert Owen promoted utopian community building, and Thomas Skidmore promoted proto-socialist ideals such as the collective ownership of businesses. While Wilentz notes that there were numerous social cleavages among workers in nineteenth century New York—ethnic, religious, economic, and linguistic—that often created divides among urban workers, there were many moments of crisis that brought these groups together to form cooperative organizations that promoted the Republican ideal of civic virtue and collective interest. To say the least, this notion of republicanism is very different from the republicanism envision by the Harvard school of thought.
          Other scholars have used the history of slavery, the Civil War, and the Civil Rights movement as another means to attack the liberal consensus and identify places where republican values have existed. While America is historically a liberal polity for white males, this has not been the case for the African American community and arguably the entire South where slavery was a cornerstone of the foundations of the political economy up until the 1860’s. Defenders of slavery often used anti-liberal ideas such as racism and neo-feudalism to support the institution. The Southern intellectual George Fitzhugh, in his 1854 work The Sociology for the South, argues:
The negro is improvident; will not lay up in the summer for wants of winter; will not accumulate in youth for the exigencies of age. He would become an insufferable burden to society. Society has the right to prevent this, and can only do this by subjecting him to domestic slavery. (Fitzhugh, 1854)

The persistence of anti-liberal and racist ideas well after the end of the Civil War throughout the period of Jim Crow segregation is not only problematic for defenders of the liberal consensus but Harvard Republicanism as well. By arguing that liberalism took hold of the population by the early 1800’s, they fail to explain the persistence of anti-liberal institutions such as slavery and Jim Crow. Even in the North during the crisis over slavery, defenders of the union and liberal democracy were conflicted over how to deal with the issue. According to the author David Greenstone, northern liberals were divided between humanists and reformers. Liberal humanists such as the Democratic politician Stephen Douglas believed that individual states should be able to vote to determine whether or not slavery would exist in their territory (Greenstone, 1993). His humanist reasoning is based on the idea that the majority of the community should be able to decide the nature of their society even if this leads to the oppression of a minority. For Stephen Douglas, this would preserve the Union. However, reformers such as Abraham Lincoln had a different perspective. Lincoln felt that slavery was immoral, and he believed that the growing divide over the issue would destroy the union. For Lincoln, preserving the union between the North and South was the most important priority, and this meant tolerating slavery in the short term while seeking to prevent its spread elsewhere and gradually destroying it where it existed. While Lincoln espoused the ideals of liberalism such as capitalism and democracy, he mixed those ideas with the Yankee moralism found in the North and republican ideals of virtue. Lincoln believed in a society where individuals could freely compete economically and politically, but he also believed that free and fair competition could not exist with an institution like slavery. A virtuous nation must eliminate vices found in the population to ensure that citizens can compete freely. Slavery was corrosive to liberal institutions and needed to be gradually extinguished. By using the writings and speeches of Lincoln as historical resources, Greenstone shows how reform liberalism, or progressivism, is a strand of liberal thought that is influenced by republican notions of virtue. He also argues that this form of liberalism is also found among progressive reformers of the twentieth century and civil rights activists.  It exemplifies how American political thought has been influenced by republican ideals, and also shows that there is a lack of consensus over the true nature of liberalism within the culture. In light of the growing partisan divide between conservatives and progressive liberals in the last forty years, it puts the entire notion of there being a liberal consensus in doubt.
         While republicanism became a popular trend among scholars from the 1970’s to the 1990’s, the movement has had its critiques (Nelson, 2017). Supporters of the liberal consensus have attacked republicanism on a number of fronts. They argue that scholars in the field have exaggerated the extant of republican ideals within the culture and the political system. For example, a supporter of the liberal consensus might argue that the Working Man’s Party and radical thinkers like Thomas Skidmore were political failures and exerted little influence at the local level in New York never mind the entire country. Furthermore, in response to criticism over the existence of non-liberal ideas in the culture, supporters of the liberal consensus have responded by claiming that America is relatively liberal in comparison with Europe despite past examples of inequality. For example, scholars such as Hartz have argued that the Federalist policy of restricting the vote to white males who owned land would have actually made them very liberal in the context of politics in England and especially in continental Europe. Since far more Americans owned land as a percentage of the population in comparison with Europe and far more people had a basic education, these restrictions on voting would not have been as severe as in England or France. Finally, critics of republicanism have argued that the school of thought lacks cohesion. The concept does not have a precise definition and has been applied to a great diversity of different movements in American history. How can republicanism describe the political culture of federalists who want to restrict the poor from voting but also apply the same concepts to socialist movements in the industrial age seeking to redistribute wealth or progressives who struggled for the civil rights of minorities and women in the 1960’s? A standardization of terminology is needed in this debate if we are to move forward on some of the pressing questions in the field.

Gordon Wood’s Republicanism
         Having established the nature of the scholarly debate between supporters of the liberal consensus and republicanism, it is now possible to discuss Gordon Wood’s work within its proper context. Wood was a student of Bernard Bailyn at Harvard University when he earned his PhD in the 1960’s, and he then became a professor at the University of Brown. Over the following four decades, Wood wrote many articles and books on the subject of republicanism and the American Revolution. His two most famous works are The Creation of the American Republic: 1776-1787, which was published in 1969, and The Radicalism of the American Revolution, which was published in 1991 (Wood, 1969; Wood, 1991). The former work analyzes the political innovations of American politicians throughout the course of the Revolutionary War, and the later book analyzes the evolution of America’s political culture from the seventeenth to the early nineteenth century. These works will be used to critique two of Wood’s following theories: (1) republicanism was a critical stage in the development of the country’s political culture from that of a monarchy to a democracy, and (2) the American Revolution was the critical event in that political transformation.
         One of the more controversial ideas in Wood’s work his defense of the idea that the Thirteen Colonies initially had a political culture that was dominated by traditional notions of monarchy, aristocracy, and dependency. According to Wood:
Despite all the momentous transformations that had taken place since the seventeenth-century settlements, mid-eighteenth-century colonial society was in many ways still traditional—traditional in its basic social relations and in its cultural consciousness. All aspects of life were intertwined. The household, society, and the state—private and public spheres—scarcely seemed separable. (Wood, 1991, 11)

In other words, Wood is arguing that America was a traditional monarchy in its early stages of development as a colony of Great Britain. It is important to note that Wood admits that the English political culture was very different from the absolute monarchies on the European continent (Wood, 1969, 3). While France had a king that held absolute power before 1789, the English monarch was bound to a constitution—a group of documents that includes the Magna Carta, the English Bill of Rights, and prior acts of Parliament. The King could not act without parliament’s consent. Nevertheless, Wood also claims that the English monarchy still exerted a heavy influence on British society and the colonies. Even though colonial society was far more egalitarian than Great Britain, people still considered themselves to be English subjects of the king. Newspapers obsessed over the gossip surrounding the royal family, and people regularly honored them by throwing parties during important events such as the accession of a new monarch. Colonists considered themselves to be personal dependents of the king and part of greater social hierarchy. More importantly, the English monarchy also exerted its influence over the colonies through the appointment of governors; most colonies were founded on royal charters. 
         According to Wood, aristocrats also exerted a strong influence on the political culture on both sides of the Atlantic in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries (Wood, 1991, 24-42). Aristocrats in England were first born sons who inherited their landholdings in tact from their fathers through a system called primogeniture. The farmers who worked these lands were often indebted to these aristocrats, so they served their lord in exchange for protection. Since large landowners had a large number of dependents who paid them rents off the land, they were able to live a life free of manual labor. While landowners often mingled with the farmers and other laborers who served them, they made sure to keep themselves socially distinct. Aristocrats were given an education, they wore expensive clothing, and lived in luxurious homes. In seventeenth-century English society, being a merchant was still a trade that was frowned down upon the elites. A true aristocrat did not want to be seen engaging in any form of labor. While Wood does admit that the influence of aristocracy was much stronger within England where land ownership was far less equal, this did not stop many wealthy Americans from trying to imitate their lifestyle. In colonial society, many landowners attempted to live lives of leisure like true aristocrats. Colonists with large landholdings, especially in the South, were given the distinction of being gentlemen. 
         In this hierarchal social system in the colonies, Wood argues that politics was very personal and people had intimate ties of dependency with those above them and ties of patronage towards those below (Wood, 1991, 43-77). Only the patriarch of the family—the land owner—represented the family to the outside world through participation in politics. Everyone else was subordinate to the male landowner and dependent on his patronage for their survival. Women had very few rights and had restrictions on their lives in terms of divorce and landownership. The role of females were to raise the children and take care of the household. Moreover, fathers were dominate over their children, and they often used coercion and abuse to regulate their lives. Even adult children were subjected to a patriarch’s authority. The eldest son often had to wait until they were middle aged before the patriarch died and they could inherit their land. There were other forms of dependency in the colonies. Many Europeans traveled to the New World as indentured servants. In exchange for paying for their passage to the new world, they normally served their master for approximately seven years before being given their freedom and a tract of land. Others came to the New World by force as slaves from West Africa mainly to work on plantations in the South growing cash crops such as tobacco, cotton, and sugar. Of course, slavery for these forced migrants was often permanent and was usually passed down to their children. Even small landowners, artisans, and free laborers found themselves in situations where they were dependent on the patronage of gentlemen. Small landowners often had problems with debt, and in an early colonial society where bank loans and money were relatively rare, they found themselves at the mercy of wealthy landlords for loans. Small landowners also lacked access to overseas markets where cash crops were traded in the triangular trade. They were usually dependent on a small handful of wealthy merchants in the coastal urban centers such as Boston, New York, Philadelphia, and Charleston for access to overseas trade. Furthermore, artisans often found themselves dependent on the patronage of gentlemen in the production of household goods and clothing since wealthy landowners were their main customers. There was also a lack of equality within the artisan profession as a young man often had to indebt themselves to a master craftsmen for several years as an apprentice before they could become independent. There was no conception of free labor like what would later appear in the nineteenth century. Both colonial and English society were places where the great majority of people were dependents in a hierarchal system.
         For these reasons according to Wood, the great majority of adults did not take part in politics in the English speaking world; instead, the government was controlled by a small handful of powerful families (Wood, 1991,77-92). In England, half of parliament was controlled by the House of Lords, which consisted of peers or hereditary landowners. The other half of parliament was controlled by the House of Commons. While this later branch of parliament had a far larger constituency who could vote and run for office, property ownership was still a prerequisite for direct participation. Only a small percentage of the population could participate in politics consequently. Voting in England was not open to all adult males until the late nineteenth century. Furthermore, while the colonists did have their own local legislatures, land ownership was a prerequisite to vote and run for office; acts of British parliament were also enforced on the colonies even though colonists did not have representatives in parliament overseas. 
         This traditional monarchial system also had no distinctions between the private and public sphere, which made the political system very different from our present conceptions of a modern state (Wood, 1991-77-92). In the colonies, powerful landholders often had multiple positions within the government, and they used those positions of power to enact policies that benefited their extended family. To keep their dependents loyal, they staffed bureaucracies with members of their patronage network. In the late seventeenth century, the population of the Thirteen Colonies was still very small, so politics was a very personal affair between powerful families in small communities. A few elite families competed to influence the legislature and the bureaucracies. What we see as corruption today was seen as normal politics from the traditional colonial perspective. In fact, a representative or a bureaucrat who did not use his political position to benefit his patronage network would have been seen as not meeting his obligations to those that depended on him for their survival. According to Wood, the colonial political system was very differently from the liberal democratic system described by De Tocqueville in the 1830’s.
         Wood also asserts that the colonists were heavily dependent on their mother country economically (Wood, 1991, 43-56). In the seventeenth century, there was very little internal monetary trade within the Thirteen Colonies, and local farmers obtained most of their goods through bartering. Most monetary and long distance trade was overseas where wealthy merchant families would exchange primary goods such as cash crops, fur, and timber for finished goods in England and slaves in West Africa. The English government preferred to keep the colonies dependent on the mother country. This decision was based on the economic theory of mercantilism. This is the belief that a country’s main economic concern should be to maximize the export of finished goods and the import of gold and silver. To do this, merchant trade needed to be regulated to prevent businessmen from importing goods from foreign countries. If a country needed natural resources, they should establish colonies in different parts of the world rather than trade with a political competitor to obtain those goods lest they enrich an enemy. For this reason, mercantilism kept the Thirteen Colonies in a state of economic dependency. 
         While the values of monarch, aristocracy, and dependency initially dominated colonial life, Wood argues that they were slowly being undermined by new social forces that are best described as republican: 
In the end the disintegration of the traditional eighteenth-century monarchical society of paternal and dependent relationships prepared the way for the emergence of the liberal, democratic, capitalistic world of the early nineteenth century. This reordering of the society of the ancient regime was not confined to America, or even to the English-speaking world. It occurred throughout Western society, sometimes but not always accompanied by violent revolution. (Wood, 1991, 95)

Within Europe and the colonies, many economic changes were happening that would lead to erosion of patronage networks and ties to monarchies. One of the most important changes was the commercial revolution, which witnessed the growth in the size of cities and long distance trade. As more peasants began to migrate to cities they began to break their old ties of dependency to their land lords. Furthermore, as long distance trade networks became increasingly important parts of the economy, merchants grew wealthier and more powerful. New innovations led to the rise in importance of banking and joint stock companies, which gave entrepreneurs a greater ability to make money. Many colonies in the New World were founded by joint-stock companies seeking to make a profit overseas. This growing class of merchants and entrepreneurial landowners wanted freedom from monarchial control to trade and produce goods to increase their profits. They argued for the efficacy of capitalism, which is the ideal that free markets maximize the efficiency of trade and production. The spread of capitalism also had an impact on the culture. While aristocrats valued a life of leisure, capitalists valued hard work and ingenuity.
         According to Wood, these economic changes were also producing social changes through the creation of a middle class. Entrepreneurial landowners, businessmen, merchants, lawyers, and other white collar professionals began to invest more in a liberal education for their children. While a traditional monarchial society demanded obedience from children, a middle class society of capitalists promoted free thought and creativity. According to John Locke, a liberal education meant that children shouldn’t be coerced into learning through force but instead convinced to learn through rational means. As a result of these social changes, individuals also began to question the dominance of Catholic priests in terms of their control of interpreting the bible. This is why the commercial revolution coincided with the Protestant Reformation and the rise in the number of churches that promoted the importance of individual interpretation of the bible and one’s personal connection with God. Furthermore, the growth in importance of schools and universities led to the scientific revolution, which resulted in innovations in trade, transport, production, and medicine that improved the quality of people’s lives. Over time, the middle class grew wealthier and were able to consume like aristocrats, which lessened the social distinctions between the two groups. 
         With these socioeconomic changes also came political changes according to Wood. Growing middle classes throughout Europe and the colonies began to pressure their governments to expand voting rights and create constitutions that upheld the liberal values of civil liberties, political rights, and the rule of law. Well-educated reformers of the Enlightenment began to question the dominance of monarchs and aristocrats based on the notion that they had special blood (Wood, 1991, 145-68). From this perspective, men of talent and ambition should be able to freely compete politically without being restrained by traditional notions of hierarchy. This led to the formation of protest movements to pressure governments to enact reforms that would promote equality and pluralism. At times, monarchies responded to this pressure by making gradual reforms through the slow expansion of suffrage. In other occasions, these pressures exploded in the form of popular revolutions such as what happened in France in 1789. By the nineteenth century, democracy began to spread on the European continent and in the New World.
         A central tent of Wood’s thesis though is that republicanism was an intermediate stage in the Thirteen Colonies transformation from a political culture dominated by the values of monarchy to an independent country dominated by the values of liberal democracy and equality. According to Wood,
Indeed, the late eighteenth century in the Atlantic world has been called “the age of the democratic revolution.” It might better be called “the age of the republican revolution.” For it was republicanism and republican principles that ultimately destroyed this monarchical society (Wood, 1991).

As the middle class grew in England and the colonies, the monarchy in England first became republicanized. The growing middle class placed pressure on the English monarchs to make political reforms to allow for their participation in government. Following the Glorious Revolution of 1688, the enactment of the English Bill of Rights significantly weakened the power of the British monarchy and gave substantial powers to the House of Commons in Parliament. Even though the colonies were influenced by traditional notions of monarchy and aristocracy, they also had their own elected legislatures dominated by white male landowners. While civil liberties such as freedom of speech and religion were granted to the population, only males who owned property could participate in the political system. Politicians that supported the middle class did not want to extend voting rights to those below them.
         Throughout the seventh and eighteenth century, the aristocracy also gradually became truncated in both England and the Colonies (Wood, 1991, 109-124). A normal aristocracy in a traditional monarchical system is based on hereditary rights and is not open to social climbers, but a truncated aristocracy grants more leeway for men of talent and ambition to purchase land and become gentlemen. Colonial society in particular was becoming more socially mobile due to Western expansion and access to new lands. If a son was dissatisfied with his father’s way of managing the household, he had the option of taking a risk by leaving the family and obtaining cheap land on the Western frontier. People who were once dependent for their survival on a wealthy gentleman could escape their positions of subservience and obtain independence through geographic mobility. This seriously weakened the bonds that existed between patrons and dependents. Throughout the eighteenth century, America grew rapidly economically and demographically, which offered greater opportunities to ambitious white males to own land and become prosperous. Many of these upstarts were resentful of gentlemen who inherited their lands and political offices due to their birthright and their connections with the English monarchy. (Wood, 1969, 67). Numerous Founding Fathers, including John Adams, Alexander Hamilton, and Benjamin Franklin, worked in a variety of professions that traditional aristocrats disparaged, and only after accumulating enough wealth were they able to settle down in the country and imitate the lives of gentlemen. 
          According to Wood, most members of this truncated aristocracy did not want to expand suffrage to the whole population (Wood, 1991, 189-212). While the founding fathers detested the monarchical and aristocratic notions of political power through birthright, they did believe in the notion that men of talent and virtue should dominate government. From their perspective, only a man that no longer has to worry about making money should serve in the government lest he uses his political office for private gain. At the same time, the founders also detested the corruption and abuse of political office in monarchical systems, and they felt that politicians should neither take a salary nor should they serve in multiple offices. This new class of enlightened politicians began to preach the republican virtues of civic virtue and patriotism, and they rejected the corruption and self-interest of the aristocracy and monarchy. Furthermore, the founders believed that men of wealth should become patrons of the arts and sciences, and they should use their wealth to educate promising young men of talent and ambition. In the process, they sought to suppress democratic forces from below that were calling for universal suffrage.
         For Wood, it is these growing republican values that eventually led to America’s revolution and the rapid political transformation of the country from 1763 to 1787. Supporters of the liberal consensus see the American Revolution as a conservative movement to protect the country’s liberal political system from English attempts to centralize control of the colonies following the end French and Indian War in 1763; however, Wood sees the political upheaval as a radical political and social movement to overthrow a traditional monarchial political system and replace it with a system based on republican values. The founders were certainly inspired by republican aspects of the English political system in their calls for revolution, but what made the American Revolution radical in Wood’s opinion was its rejection of monarchy and the traditional social bonds that uphold this political system. Paradoxically, Americans were calling for revolution by appealing to aspects of the political system they were seeking to overthrow:
They sincerely believed they were not creating new rights or new principles prescribed only by what ought to be, but saw themselves claiming “only to keep their old privileges,” the traditional rights and principles of all Englishmen….Yet, this continual talk of desiring nothing new and wishing only to return to the old system and the essentials of the English constitution was only a superficial gloss. The Americans were rushing into revolution even as they denied it, their progress both obscured and sustained by a powerful revolutionary ideology.”(Wood, 1969, 13).

In the writings of pamphleteers such as Thomas Paine, we see how the legitimacy of monarchy and aristocracy in the culture collapsed while colonists were simultaneously supporting its republican aspects. Sovereignty was vested in the monarch under the old colonial system, but sovereignty became vested in the American people—specially, white male landowners—following independence.
         In Wood’s book The Creation of the American Republic, he attempts to show how the founding fathers engaged in radical political experiments and attempted to establish utopian political communities (Wood, 1991). During the course of the revolution in 1775, state governments throughout America began to establish new local governments that made use of radical political innovations. They rejected the legitimacy of governors appointed by the monarchy, and they created new legislatures that had significantly more power than before. Furthermore, these new legislatures created voting districts based on their actual population so that politicians represented a relatively equal number of voters. This differed from England where voting districts had drastically different populations; furthermore, representation in England was virtual in that politicians in the House of Commons were considered to represent the general interests of the middle class and not their specific constituents. In fact, the British defended taxation without direct representation by claiming that colonists were represented by parliament virtually and not directly. In contrast, American patriots such as Thomas Paine and Patrick Henry argued that representation needed to be direct. Furthermore, new state governments promoted a conception of separation of powers that was different from the past. In England, separation of powers meant a division of power between the monarchy, the aristocracy, and the commons; in America, it came to mean the division between the legislative, executive and judicial branches similar to the Roman Republic. In England, the monarchy held the power of the executive, but in the new state legislatures in America governors were voted in by the land owning population. Furthermore, bicameralism in England meant dividing parliament into the House of Lords, which represented the aristocracy, and the House of Commons, which represented the middle class. During the revolution, bicameralism in America came to mean having one house where politicians represented districts of equal population and another house that represented different regions of the state based on their economic differences. The colonists deliberately eliminated notions of monarchy and aristocracy from their new political systems. 
         In his book The Radicalism of the American Revolution, Wood not only claims that America’s revolution was radical politically but socially as well (Wood, 1969). Following the attempt by the British government to impose direct taxes on the colonies in 1763, protest movements grew larger and more violent over the ensuing decade. As the protests intensified, society became divided by patriots that wanted separation from Britain and loyalists that wanted to remain in the British Empire. Facing violence and persecution, tens of thousands of loyalist fled the country. While scholars of the liberal consensus have claimed that America’s revolution was relatively conservative in comparison with the more violent revolts that took place in France and Russia, Wood is claiming that there were social divides in revolutionary America that led to political unrest. 
         More importantly for Wood, the revolution led to long term social changes that would lead to the decline of not only monarchial but republican values and the spread of liberalism. During the revolution, the new American government needed to supply its army, so they issued loans to farmers in the form of bonds. This introduced many Americans to paper money and banking for the first time. The revolution also resulted in America’s economic separation from England. This forced the colonists to focus on domestic as opposed to international trade. The newly independent country developed their own system of banking, and they invested in an internal infrastructure to facilitate trade. In the decades following the revolution, large number of Americans moved out West own land, and they increasingly used banks and paper money to invest in a great variety of business ventures. America’s rapid economic growth led to the creation of a very large and mobile middle class that preached the liberal democratic values of equality, capitalism, and pluralism. While the commercial revolution began before the founding of the colonies, no other country at that point in world history had a middle class that was as large and mobile like the United States by the early 1800’s. As the middle class grew, they began to question the republican notion that only gentlemen of high standing should be in politics. Wood even goes as far as to claim that the revolution set the stage for the development of movements that would liberate African Americans and women. The revolution led to a lot of violent protests, and it inspired many people to participate in politics. 
         Republicanism did not go down without a struggle according to Wood. Federalists in 1787 attempted to suppress the growing support for liberal democracy by creating a constitution that placed limits on popular participation.  Nevertheless, the federalists were fighting a losing battle. As America continued to expand out West and grow economically, its middle class grew in size and became distrustful of well-educated elites, who were seen to serve not the interests of the public as a whole but their own selfish interests. Anti-federalists argued that Federalists were using republicanism as a means to entrench themselves into power. From the liberal perspective, all individuals—no matter how well educated they are— have their own selfish interests. Therefore, politicians should represent the constituents who voted for them and not the whole nation. In a pluralistic society, a government should represent the heterogeneous interests of its citizens. By the early nineteenth century, Wood argues that republican values faded away and were replaced with the values of a liberal, pluralistic society. 
  
A Critique of Gordon Wood: Conceptualizing Regime Type
         Is Gordon Wood’s or Louis Hartz’s characterization of American political culture more accurate? Or are there serious flaws with both theories? There are numerous problems that confront a scholar that attempts to answer this question. One can argue that proponents of the liberal consensus and republicanism have mined for quotes from historical resources to construct narratives that fit their respective theories. The problem with doing this is that it makes one’s theory unfalsifiable. The mere existence of ideas in the culture does not tell us if those ideas were widespread and dominant within the political system or if those ideas were only accepted by a small minority of individuals. One can find plenty of examples of liberal ideas within American culture prior to the American Revolution, and examples of republican ideals in its aftermath. The relevant question is which ideas were dominant at which times, and what impact did these ideas have on American politics and society? Another problem within this debate is the conceptual stretching of terminology. Supporters of the liberal consensus claim America’s culture was more liberal than that of Europe from the beginnings of its history; however, being more liberal than an authoritarian regime does not necessarily mean we can classify a country’s political culture as being democratic or that there has always been a liberal consensus within a country. We need to clearly define political culture by a set of rigorous standards if we are to have a debate on this issue.
         So what exactly is a political culture? According to David Elkins and Richard Semeon, political culture is the beliefs, rules, and traditions within a community that determine who gets to rule (Elkins and Semeon, 1979). The political culture gives a regime legitimacy. According to Gerardo Munck, the political regime is the formal and informal rules within society for determining who gets to create, enforce, and interpret the laws (Munck, 1996). While various factions in society may disagree with the rules of a regime and want to change those rules, the regime exists because it has legitimacy with a large portion of the population. While supporters of the state can use violence and co-optation to keep the government in power, a regime becomes stable when it has legitimacy with the majority of the population. This legitimacy is created through the propagation of ideas that justify the existence of the current political system. For example, traditional monarchies propagate the idea that those in power have special blood and deserve to rule based on their lineage. In contrast, liberal democracies promote Lockian notions of liberty and equality. To determine which set of ideas have been dominant in the American political culture, it is imperative to clearly define America’s political regime at various points in its history. By clearly defining the regime, we will have a standard by which we can say that a set of political values were dominant at a specific period of time. 
         This is why it is critical to first classify the different types of political regimes if we are to construct a theory of American political culture that is falsifiable. There are three regime types: democratic, semi-authoritarian, and authoritarian. On the most liberal side of the spectrum are democratic regimes, which are political systems in which the government is ruled—at least ideally—by the people. According to Leanardo Morlino, there are five main procedural dimensions that are necessary to classify a regime as a democracy: the rule of law, transparency/accountability, political responsiveness, political rights, and civil liberties (Morlino, 2004). For a society to be democratic, citizens must be considered equal under the law regardless of their race, ethnicity, language, or gender, and due process must be equitable and just. Furthermore, citizens must have political rights such as the ability to vote, run for office, and form political organizations, and they require civil liberties like freedom of speech, religion, and the press. In addition, the actions of government must be transparent to the public, and citizens should be able to hold their representatives accountable through the ballot box. Scholars have added other attributes. For example, Seymour Lipset believes that democracies must survive long enough to become consolidated and institutionalized (Lipset, 1994). Following a revolution, many young democracies have failed and returned to authoritarianism due to the lack of institutionalization and acceptance from the public. Furthermore, Wolfgang Merkel also argues that economic development and economic equality are critical for the long term stability of democratic institutions (Markel, 2007). Of course, no democracy fully meets these idealistic expectations, and some of these attributes (such as economic equality) may be stretching the concept. Robert Dahl argues that we should instead use the word polyarchy to describe democracies, which simply means that multiple groups contest for control of the state through elections. According to Dahl, no democracy has perfect equality between citizens as certain individuals and groups will always have greater access to the state than others.  
         Other attributes commonly found in democracies are not necessary components of these political systems(Collier and Lavitsky, 1997). For example, some democratic systems are presidential in nature in that they have horizontal checks and balances between the legislative, executive, and judicial branches. In contrast, most of Europe’s democratic systems have the powers of the legislative and executive branches fused in a parliamentary system of government. Furthermore, some democracies such as the United States and Great Britain promote the ideals of capitalism and free market policies whereas continental European democracies tend to promote coordinated market economies and collectivism. Some democracies such as the United States have federal political systems where some power is devolved to the sub units at the local level whereas other countries such as France have unitary systems where power is concentrated in the central government. None of these attributes are necessary to be labeled as democratic. Instead, what all of these democratic regimes have in common today is that they have relatively free and fair elections, voting rights for the adult population, and the protection of basic civil liberties and political rights. To justify the existence of these regimes, political elites have promoted Lockian political ideals such as civil liberties and political rights. 
         At the other end of the spectrum are authoritarian regimes, which consist of small groups of individuals who have monopolized power and a political culture that promotes hierarchy and dependency (Munck, 1996). Those on top of the hierarchy create, enforce, and interpret the rules. This does not mean that those on top of the hierarchy can do what they want. The legitimacy of an authoritarian regime often depends on its ability to maintain political, economic, and social stability. Furthermore, authoritarian regimes are diverse. A traditional authoritarian system such as that described by Gordon Wood uses ideals such as monarchy, aristocracy, and patriarchy to defend the lack of equality in society and the need for hierarchy. France prior to 1789 is a classic example of traditional monarchy. However, modern authoritarian systems such as one-party dictatorships, personalistic dictatorships and military dictatorships have different ideals underpinning their legitimacy. For example, one party dictatorships such as that of the communist party regimes of the twentieth century based their legitimacy on the promise of future economic prosperity to their populations. These authoritarian governments claimed that they would use rational, scientific principles to foster economic development. Personal rights needed to be sacrificed to insure political stability and economic growth. What all authoritarian regimes have in common is that they had political culture that promotes hierarchy and subordination. Power is not determined through contested elections but by a small group of elites who make decisions about the country behind closed doors. Prior to the enlightenment, traditional authoritarian systems dominated political cultures throughout the world. 
         While some regimes are relatively easy to classify as democratic or authoritarian, other regimes are more difficult to label (Merkel, 2007). The enlightenment in seventeenth and eighteenth century Europe ushered in an era of revolutions and political activists calling for liberal political reforms; however, democratization has not been a quick or even process throughout the globe. While many authoritarian regimes have been forced to open up their political systems to electoral contestation since the seventeenth century, some groups have been strategically excluded from this process of democratization. For example, America’s political system in 1791 excluded landless white males, women, African Americans, and Native Americans from the political process initially. Political systems with contested elections that exclude demographically significant groups are semi-authoritarian regimes. These hybrid political cultures combine the liberal rhetoric of Locke with authoritarian political rhetoric that justifies the exclusion of some people from the political process. For example, republicanism has been used to justify the exclusion of the poor from decision making in government. However, republicanism is not the only ideology that has justified exclusion throughout out American history. Racism, bigotry, and economic justifications for slavery have been used to exclude African Americans from the political process in the United States. Patriarchy has been used to justify the exclusion of women, and nativism has been used to justify the exclusion of newly arrived immigrants. From the semi-authoritarian perspective, only those who belong to superior groups should have civil liberties and political rights. This explains why founding fathers such as Thomas Jefferson could espouse both the liberal values of John Locke and also promote republicanism and the necessity of slavery at the same time. In a semi-authoritarian regime, liberal values only apply to certain groups. Far from being contradictory, the coexistence of liberal and authoritarian rhetoric is what gives legitimacy to a semi-authoritarian regime. When Thomas Jefferson claimed that all men are equal, it was assumed he was speaking of white landowning males.
         This is why the liberal consensus theory is seriously flawed. By using a relativistic argument to claim that America was always a liberal society because it was not as authoritarian as feudal France, it neglects the fact that the majority of Americans were still excluded from the political system prior to, during, and after the American Revolution. The liberal political culture described by De Tocqueville did not apply to over half the population. The exclusion of groups such as landless white males, African Americans, and women also set the stage for conflict later in American history, which contradicts the notion of the existence of liberal consensus since the country’s founding. These conflicts included the bloody American civil war as well as the civil rights movement of the 1950’s and 1960’s. It is not until the last half century that America has come close to fulfilling Morlino’s idealistic definition of a democracy.
         How then shall we explain the dominance of capitalism and America’s relatively weak welfare state and labor movement in comparison with Europe? Is America’s political culture more capitalistic because it never had a feudal class structure and was born a democracy, or is there another explanation? According to Alberto Alessina and Edward Glaeser, America does not have a weaker welfare state because of the entrenchment of capitalist ideals since the founding of the country (Alessina and Glaeser, 2004). They argue that America’s lack of welfare state and the dominance of capitalist ideals among the elite are a result of two factors: America’s political institutions such as its presidential system and majoritarian electoral system, and America’s salient ethnic cleavage between whites and blacks. 
         Paradoxically, America’s earlier transition to a more open political system than most of Europe may have negatively effected progressive liberal reforms in the distant future. American’s republican constitution has a lot of checks and balances, which has made it easier for wealthy special interests to block political reforms. Furthermore, its single member district majoritarian electoral system has led to a two party system that has blocked third parties from gaining an influence on the legislature. Conservatives promoting the status quo have had a greater influence on the political system as a result. In contrast, most states in Europe underwent democratization much later from the late nineteenth century to the post World War II era, and they established political systems that made it easier for the popular majority to control the government. Proportional electoral systems in Europe made it easier for third parties representing the interest of labor unions to establish their influence on the political system, and parliamentary systems provide fewer veto points by which special interests can manipulate the government. All it takes I simple majority in most European systems to pass reforms to expand the welfare state. The reason for the differences in these systems is the timing: America developed its democratic institutions at a time when giving the wealthy minority disproportionate power was still legitimate. Since the constitution is more entrenched within the American political system due to its long lifespan, American business elites have been more effective at blocking welfare legislation historically. They have used their dominance to amass more wealth and influence the country’s media outlets and educational institutions, which have promoted capitalist rhetoric to protect their interests. In contrast, governments in Western Europe have been heavily influenced by left wing political parties and labor unions, who have had a heavier influence on the educational system and the media. From Glaesar’s and Alessina’s perspective, Americans are against redistribution not because they have a longer history of liberalism but because their republican constitution has stalled political reforms and entrenched the economic elites into power.
         The other factor that has influenced the entrenchment of capitalist rhetoric in America is the saliency of the black/white cleavage. European states are generally more homogeneous than the United States. Furthermore, the states in Europe that do have ethnic diversity do not have massive wealth gaps between majority and minority groups. The United States has a very different history. Due to slavery and Jim Crow, the United States has had an ethnic minority that is much poorer than the ethnic majority. As a result, poverty in the United States is often conflated with race. In America, opportunistic political entrepreneurs on the right have used ethnic animosity to convince poor whites to vote against welfare state reforms and the redistribution of wealth to the poor. While the amount of biological racism has declined in the United States since the 1960’s, a new form of racial prejudice called symbolic racism has become prevalent amongst conservative whites. Many conservatives are resentful of the black minority and feel that the government wrongfully redistributes wealth to minorities. Instead of blaming the economic problems in the black community on slavery and Jim Crow, they blame it it on a culture of entitlement within the black community. This makes wealthy whites in the United States less likely than their European counterparts to empathize with the poor. 
         Therefore, the entrenchment of capitalism in America’s political culture is not a product of a liberal consensus that has dominated the country since its founding. Instead, it is the product of an entrenched republican constitution and racial resentment. While America may have been more liberal than Europe in the late eighteenth century, by the end of the twentieth century, Western European countries were more equal politically and economically.
         Gordon Wood’s critique of American political culture does address some of these problems with the liberal consensus, but his republican theory also suffers from a number of flaws. First, his characterization of American political culture as authoritarian prior to the American revolution neglects to point out the liberal aspects of the political culture that have existed since its founding. While he is correct to point at the existence of patriarchy, slavery, and monarchial values within the colonies prior to the revolution, this neglects the fact that colonial legislatures had competitive elections between white male land owners. American revolutionaries were also influenced ideologically by the English Bill of Rights and the Glorious Revolution. He also overemphasizes the influence of the monarchy on colonial political culture. The great distance between Britain and the colonies significantly weakened the influence of the king on colonial politics—at least until 1763 when the British government attempted to assert itself more directly on colonial politics. Additionally, Wood exaggerates the impact of the revolution on the American political regime in the decades that followed independence. It is true that the revolution led to the severing of ties with the British monarchy and led to substantial changes in the country’s political institutions. The revolution inspired Americans to become politically active, and future generations would use the rhetoric of the founding fathers to justify progressive democratic reforms. However, America did not establish a liberal democracy that included all demographically significant groups in the system following independence from Great Britain. One of the great weakness’ of Wood’s analysis of America’s political culture is his description of women’s rights and slavery in the aftermath of the revolution. While one can argue that the status of women improved after 1776 as they were more easily able to own land and divorce following post-revolutionary reforms, women still didn’t gain the right to vote until 1919. While northern states outlawed slavery in the decades following the revolution, slavery continued in the Southern States until 1865, and this was followed by a century of Jim Crow laws in the South. The Civil Rights Act and the Voting Rights Act to protect the civil liberties and political rights of African Americans did not pass until 1964 and 1965. While the American revolution was an important event in American history, it did not lead to a full transition to a liberal democracy. Instead, it would take two centuries for minority groups to become more included in the political system, and the country still struggles with meeting the ideal standards of Morlino’s definition of a democracy today given the persistence of illiberal institutions such as the electoral college and the enormous wealth gap between rich and poor.

Conclusion
         There are several conclusions to draw from this analysis of American political culture. First, proponents of the liberal consensus are right that America is unique in that it experienced a relatively earlier transition to a political system that had contested elections. Furthermore, they are right to argue that America’s transition to democracy began long before the American revolution. Liberal Lockian ideals took hold of the culture long before they significantly influenced most other countries in Western Europe. However, they are wrong to claim that America’s political system has been dominated by a liberal political consensus as the ideals of John Locke have often been qualified by authoritarian rhetoric justifying the dominance of wealthy white males in the political system. These authoritarian ideals, as shown by Gordon Wood, were present prior to the revolution. The contradiction between these ideals has been a source of conflict—a conflict which continues to the present. America may not have had a long history of intense class warfare like in Europe, but class conflict has been substituted for ethnic conflict and a progressive/conservative divide over the influence of different groups on the political system. While white Protestant males had opportunities to own land and prosper early on in America’s history, the same opportunities did not exist for women and various ethnic minorities. America’s brutal civil war is a testament to the lack of consensus in America’s political culture, even if we are comparing this cultural relatively to Europe. The salient political divide between conservatives and progressives today shows that a political consensus over the nature of the country’s democracy continues to allude the political culture. 
         Furthermore, this analysis of American political culture contradicts the findings of Gordon Wood. It is clear that a liberal political consensus did not emerge from the American Revolution. While the revolution certainly led to political reforms in its aftermath, it did not come close to erasing all forms of social inequality in society. This does not mean that the revolution was not an important event in the country’s history. No revolution—even (or perhaps especially) the French, Russian, and Chinese revolutions—led to the complete elimination of all forms of authoritarianism and the establishment of a society based on the perfect ideals of political equality. Nevertheless, over ninety percent of the population was initially excluded from the political system in the aftermath of the American Revolution. In the centuries following independence, Americans continued to struggle with the question of which groups should participate in the political system.



Work Cited
2.   Alesina, Alberto, and Edward L. Glaeser. 2004. Fighting Poverty in the US and Europe: A World of Difference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
3.   Anderson, Perry.  2017. The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci.  Verso Publishing: New York.
4.   Arendt, Hannah. 2018. Thinking without a Bannister: Essays in Understanding, 1953-75. Schoken Publishing: Germany.
5.   Bailyn, Bernard and Jane Garrett. 1965. Pamphlets of the American Revolution, 1750-1776. Belknap Press: Massachusetts.
6.   Bercovitch, Sacvan. 2012. The American Jeremiad. The University of Wisconsin Press: Wisconsin.
7.   Collier, David and Steve Lavitsky. 1997. “Democracy with Adjectives: Conceptual Innovation in Comparative Research,” World Politics, 49: 430-51.
8.   De Tocqueville, Alexis. 1966. Democracy in America, Translated by George Lawrence. Harper & Row Publishers: New York.
9.   Diamond, Larry and Leonardo Morlino. 2004. “The Quality of Democracy,” Canadian Journal of Political Science, 40(4). 
10.Dienstag, Joshua Foa. 1996. “Serving God and Mammon: The Lockean Sympathy in Early American Political Thought,” The American Political Science Review, 90(3): 497-511
11.Elkins, David and Richard Simeon. 1979. “A Cause in Search of Its Effect, or What Does Political Culture Explain, Comparative Politics, 11(2): 127-45.
12.Gandhi, Jennifer and Adam Przeworski. 2007. "Authoritarian Institutions and the Survival of Autocrats," Comparative Political Studies, 40(11): 1279-1301.
13.Goldstone, Jack A., 2001. “Toward a Fourth Generation of Revolutionary Theory,” Annual Review of Political Science4, 139-187.
14.Greenstone, David. 1993. The Lincoln Persuasion: Remaking American Liberalism. Princeton University Press: New Jersey.
15.Hartz, Louis. 1955. The Liberal Tradition in America. Harvest Publishing: New York.
16.Herzog, Don. 1986. “Some Questions for Republicans,” Political Theory, 14(3): 473-93.
17.Huntington, Samuel.  Political Order in Changing Societies.  Yale University Press: New Haven, 1968.
18.Jefferson, Thomas. 1958. “The Declaration of Independence,” in Great Issues in American History by Richard Hofstadter. Alfred A. Knopf: United States.
19.Kornetis, Kostis. 2014. "1968, 1989, 2011: Reconsidering Social Movements, Moments of Change, and Theoretical Framing Over Time," Historien, 13.
20.Kroeber, Clifton B. 1996.  "Theory and History of Revolution,"Journal of World History, 7(1): 21-40.
21.Kuz, Michal. 2015. "Tocqueville's Dual Theory of Revolution," The European Legacy, 20(1) 41-55.
22.Lipset, Seymour M. “The Social Requisites of Democracy Revisited: 1993 Presidential Address,”  American Sociological Review, 59, 1994: 1-22.
23.Lipset, Seymour. 1996. American Exceptionalism: A Double-Edged Sword. W.W. Norton: New York.
24.Linz, Juan and Alfred Stepan.  "Toward Consolidated Democracies," in The Global Divergence of Democracies, edited by Larry Diamon and Marc Plattner. John Hopkins University Press: Baltimore, 93-112.
25.Lynch, Marc, ed. The Arab Uprisings Explained: New Contentious Politics in the Middle East.  Columbia University Press: New York, 2014.
26.Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. 2014. Communist Manifesto. International Publishers: United States.
27.Merkel, Wolfgang and Aurel Croissant. 2004. “Conclusions: Good and Defective Democracies,” Democratization, 11(5): 199-213.
28.Morlino, Leanardo.  "What is a Good Democracy," Democratization, 11(5), 2004: 10-32.
29.Munck, Gerardo. 1996. "Disaggregating Political Regime: Conceptual Issues in the Study of Democratization," Kellog Institute Working Paper, 228. 
30.Nail, Thomas.  "Deuluze, Occupy, and the Actuality of Revolution," Theory and Event, 16(1), 2013.
31.Nelson, Eric. 2017. “Flipping his Whigs: A Response to Gordon Wood,” https://scholar.harvard.edu/files/ericnelson/files/nelson_response_to_gordon_s_wood_.pdf.
32.O'Donnell, Guillermo and Phillip Schmitter. 1986.  Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Tentative Conclusions about Uncertain Democracies.  John Hopkins University Press: Baltimore, 3-72.
33.Paine, Thomas. 2013. Common Sense. Tribeca Books: United States.
34.Pratt, Raymond P. 1978. "Toward a Critical Theory of Revolution," Polity, 11(2), 1978: 172-99.
35.Rogers, Daniel. 1992. “Republicanism: the Career of a Concept,” The Journal of American History, 79(1): 11-38.
36.Rositer, Clinton, ed. 2003. The Federalist Papers. Signet Classics: New York. 
37.Sartori, GIovanni. 1991. "Comparing and Miscomparing," Journal of Theoretical Politics, 3(3): 243-257.
38.Schneider, Carsten and Phillipe C. Schmitter. 2004. "Liberalization, Transition, and Consolidation: Measuring the Components of Democratization," Democratization, 11(5): 59-90.
39.Tilly, Charles. 1978. From Mobilization to Revolution. Addison-Wesley Publishing: Massachusetts. 
40.Tilly, Charles. 2000. "Processes and Mechanisms of Democratization," Sociological Theory, 18(1): 1-16.
41.Wilenz, Sean. 2004. Chants Democratic: New York City and the Rise of the American Working Class, 1788-1850. Oxford University Press: Oxford.
42.Wood, Gordon. 1969.  The Creation of the American Republic: 1776-1787. Norton & Company: New York.
43.Wood, Gordon. 1991. The Radicalism of the American Revolution. Vintage Books: New York.

44. Voglis, Polymeris.  "Talkin' About a Revolution, it Sounds Like a Whisper: Theories and Debates on Social Revolutions," Historein, 13, 2014: 47-56.